THE
POLICE
ARE
INNOCENT
AS
LONG
AS
THEY
HONESTLY
BELIEVE:
THE
HUMAN
RIGHTS
PROBLEMS
WITH
ENGLISH
SELF-
DEFENSE
LAW
Clemency
Wang*
TABLE
OF
CONTENTS
Introduction.
............................................
374
I.
Background
.................................
..........
376
A.
Homicide
in
England
and
Wales
...................
.....
376
B.
Self-Defense:
A
General
Defense
to
Homicide
.......
......
378
C.
The
European
Convention
on
Human
Rights
and
the
European
Union
................
..........................
.....
380
1.
Article
2
of
the
European
Convention
.......
...........
381
2.
Human
Rights
Act
............................
.....
383
3.
European
Union
Charter
of
Fundamental
Rights
................
384
II.
Problems
..................................................
386
A.
"Honest
Belief'
and
Police
Brutality
.....................
386
B.
Unreasonable
Beliefs
and
Manslaughter......
...........
391
C.
An
Artificial
"Reasonableness"
Element
..................
394
D.
An
Obsolete
Basis
.......................................
399
III.
Potential
Solutions
..........................
.......
..........
400
A.
An
Honest
and
Reasonable
Belief
..........
.....
........
400
B.
Abolishing
Affirmative
Defense
to
Manslaughter
....
......
402
C.
Partial
Defense
of
Excessive
Self-Defense
.......
.........
402
D.
Inspiring
Reform:
The
European
Court
of
Human
Rights
......
404
1.
The
Importance
of
Positive
Obligations
in
the
ECHR..........407
*
J.D.
candidate,
Columbia
Law
School,
class
of
2018.
The
author
thanks
Professor
Harold
Edgar
(Columbia
Law
School)
and
Dr.
Jonathan
Rogers
(University
College
London).
COLUMBIA
HUMAN
RIGHTS
LAW
REVIEW
2.
The
Curious
Case
of
Armani
Da
Silva
in
2016
......
.....
410
Conclusion
.........................................
.....
413
INTRODUCTION
In
1999,
Henry
Stanley
was
carrying
a
broken
table
leg
in
a
plastic
bag
when
he
was
confronted
and
killed
by
a
police
officer
in
London,
who
genuinely
believed
he
was
in
possession
of
a
sawn-off
shotgun.'
The
police
officer
was
cleared
of
all
charges
in
the
Sharman
case
of
2005,
having
successfully
pled
self-defense,
despite
the
fact
that
such
a
belief
should
have been
found
unreasonable
by
a
vast
majority
of people.
2
In
Bennett,
a
similar
case
decided
in
2007,3
a
man
who
was
carrying
a
cigarette lighter
was
shot
dead
by
police
officers
who
thought
it
was
a
gun.
4
Self-defense is
one
of
the
oldest
affirmative
defenses
in
the
common
law,
with
roots
in
Roman
Law
principles.'
Yet,
due
to
its
uncertain
and
contentious
nature,
it
has
been
the target
of
many
attempts
at
reform
and
much
debate
over
the
past
few
decades,
especially
in
the
United
Kingdom.'
One
of
the
main
criticisms
of
the
law
of
self-defense in
the
United
Kingdom
is
that
it
takes
into
account
only
the
honest
belief
of
the
defendant
when
responding
to
a
perceived
threat,
without
regard
to
whether
such
a
perception
was
reasonable.
This
standard
was
originally
established
by
the
common
1.
R
(on
the
application
of
Sharman)
v.
HM
Coroner
for
Inner
North
London
[20051
EWCA
(Civ)
967
[1]-[9],
[2005]
Inquest
L.R.
168
(Eng.).
2.
Id.
3.
R
(on
the
application
of
Bennett)
v.
HM
Coroner
for
Inner
South
London
[2007]
EWCA
(Civ)
617
[351-[36],
[2007]
Inquest
L.R.
163
(Eng.).
4.
Id.
at
[101-[11].
5.
BRUCE
W.
FRIER
&
THOMAS
A.
MCGINN,
A
CASEBOOK
ON
ROMAN
FAMILY
LAW
193
(Joel
Lidov
ed.,
2004).
6.
See
generally
THE
LAW
COMMISSION, MURDER,
MANSLAUGHTER
AND
INFANTICIDE
128
(2006),
http://www.lawcom.gov.uk/wp-content/uploads/2015/03/
lc304_MurderManslaughter-and
InfanticideReport.pdf
[https://perma.cc/65K5-
PWKR]
(noting
the
debate about
the
"need
for
the
belief
[of
death
or
life-
threatening
harm]
to
be
reasonably
held");
Jonathan
Rogers,
Culpability
in
Self-
Defence
and
Crime
Prevention,
in
SEEKING SECURITY:
PRE-EMPTING
THE
COMMISSION
OF CRIMINAL
HARMS
265-92
(2012).
7.
Criminal
Justice
and
Immigration
Act
2008,
c.
4,
§
76
(Eng.);
R
v.
Williams
(Gladstone)
[19871
3
All
ER
411,
411,
413
(Eng.).
[49.3:1
374
As
Long
as
They
Honestly
Believe
law
in
the
notable
case
of
Regina
v.
Gladstone
Williams,'
but
the
courts
have
been
demonstrably
unwilling
to
raise
the
bar
to
a
reasonable
belief
for
criminal
cases,
choosing
to
restrict
the
"honest
and
reasonable
belief'
standard
to
self-defense
within
intentional
torts
only.
9
Furthermore,
as
of
2008,
the
standard
of
honest
belief
has
been
codified
in
Parliamentary
legislation,
which
is
the
supreme
form
of
law
in
the
United
Kingdom
due
to
the
lack
of
a
formal
written
constitution
and
the
traditional
notion
that
Parliament,
as
the
highest
legislative
body,
is
sovereign.
0
This
legislation
demonstrates
further
the
United
Kingdom's
unwillingness
to
budge
from
this
position,
despite
the
seemingly
unfair
verdicts
in
which
it
has
resulted-especially
in
the
cases
of police
officers
killing
civilians
on
the
basis
of
unreasonable
beliefs,
as
seen
above.n
This
law
has
naturally
resulted
in
human
rights
concerns,
especially
given
that
the
United
Kingdom
is
party
to
the
European
Convention
on
Human
Rights
(ECHR).1
2
The
right
to
life
is
recognized
as
a
fundamental
right.'
3
The
ECHR
sets
out
this
right
in
Article
2
of
the
Convention,
which
not
only
requires
that
signatory
parties
ensure
that
the
state
and
its
agents
do
not
unnecessarily
deprive
individuals
of
life,
but
also
imposes
upon
signatory
parties
a
positive
obligation
to
effectively
protect
individuals
from
being
killed
by
third
parties."
This
includes
enforcing
legislation
and
setting
out
laws
that
sufficiently
and
effectively
penalize
people
for
the
unnecessary
deprivation
of
life."
With
that
in
mind,
this
Note
argues
that
the
current
U.K.
laws
that
permit
attackers,
especially
police
officers,
who
made
unreasonable
mistakes
about
the
victim
being
a
threat
to
argue
self-defense,
constitute
a
blatant
violation
of
Article
2
of
the
ECHR.
It
should
have
thus
resulted
in
a
ruling
of
the
European
8.
Williams
(Gladstone),
3
All
ER
at
411.
9.
Ashley
v.
Chief
Constable
of
Sussex
[2008]
UKHL
25,
[2008]
1
AC
962
(appeal
taken
from
Eng.).
10.
Criminal
Justice
and
Immigration
Act
2008,
c.
4,
§
76
(Eng.).
11.
R
(on
the
application
of
Sharman)
v.
HM
Coroner
for
Inner
North
London
[2005]
EWCA
(Civ) 967
[11-[91,
[2005]
Inquest
L.R.
168
(Eng.).
12.
European
Convention
for
the
Protection
of
Human
Rights
and
Fundamental
Freedoms,
opened
for
signature
Nov.
4,
1950,
Europ.
T.S.
No.
5,
213
U.N.T.S.
221
(entered
into
force
Sept.
3,
1953)
[hereinafter
European
Convention].
13.
See
Universal
Declaration
of
Human
Rights,
G.A.
Res.
217A
(III),
art.
3,
U.N.
GAOR,
3d
Sess.,
U.N.
Doc.
A/810,
at
2
(Dec.
10,
1948).
14.
ANDREW
ASHWORTH,
POSITIVE
OBLIGATIONS
IN
CRIMINAL
LAW
196
(2013)
[hereinafter
POSITIVE
OBLIGATIONS].
15.
ANDREW
ASHWORTH,
PRINCIPLES
OF
CRIMINAL
LAW
238
(6th
ed.,
2009)
[hereinafter
ASHWORTH].
2018]
375
COLUMBIA
HUMAN
RIGHTS
LAW
REVIEW
Court
of
Human
Rights
requiring
the
United
Kingdom
to
amend
its
laws of
self-defense
to
satisfy
its
positive
obligations
under
Article
2
when
prompted
to
do
so
in
2016
in
Armani
Da
Silva
v.
United
Kingdom.
Part
I
of
this
Note
will provide
an
overview
of
homicide
crimes
under
the
law
of
England
and
Wales
and the
defenses
that
are
available,
with
a
particular
focus
on
self-defense
as
an
affirmative
defense
that
has
oddly
lenient requirements
compared
to
other
defenses
to
homicide
under
English
law.
It
will
also
establish the
United
Kingdom's
human
rights
obligations
that
ensure
that
the
right
to
life
of
individuals within
its
borders
be
protected
by
laws
that
effectively
punish
unjustified
homicide.
Part
II
will
identify
the
problems
that
currently
exist with
the
United
Kingdom's homicide
laws
and
argue
that
the
law
of
self-defense is
unjust
and
does
not
effectively fulfill
their
ECHR
obligation
to
protect
the
fundamental
right
to
life.
Part
III
will
analyze
potential
solutions
that
can
resolve
this
inconsistency
and
the
likelihood
of
the
adoption
of
these
solutions
in
light
of
the
existing
legal
and
political
climate
in
Europe.
I.
BACKGROUND
A.
Homicide
in
England
and
Wales
In England
and
Wales, homicide
is
mainly
separated
into
two
distinct
groups:
murder
and
manslaughter."
Murder
is defined
as
unlawfully
causing
death,
without
justification
or excuse,
with
"malice
aforethought,"
under
the
King's
peace."
"Malice
aforethought"
refers
to
the intention
to
cause
either death
or
grievous
bodily
harm
under
U.K.
case
law."
"Unlawfully"
here
refers
to
a
lack
of
justification
or excuse,
as
a
successful
demonstration
of
any
defense
will
either
reduce
a
conviction
of
murder
to
one of
manslaughter
(in
the
case
of
a
partial
defense,
such as
diminished
responsibility
or
loss of
control),
or
quash
it
altogether
(in
the
case
of
a
general
defense,
such
as self-defense).
19
A
conviction
for
murder
16.
Id.
at
237-38.
17.
SIR
EDWARD
COKE,
THE
THIRD
PART
OF
THE
INSTITUTES
OF
THE
LAWES
OF
ENGLAND:
CONCERNING
HIGH
TREASON,
AND
OTHER
PLEAS
OF
THE
CROWN,
AND
CRIMINAL
CAUSES
47
(1644).
18.
R
v.
Cunningham
[1982]
AC
566,
574
(Eng.)
(defining
grievous
bodily
harm).
19.
JAMES
RICHARDSON,
QC,
ARCHBOLD CRIMINAL
PLEADING,
EVIDENCE
AND
PRACTICE
(P.J.
Richardson
et
al.
eds.,
2009).
376
[49.3:1
As
Long
as
They
Honestly
Believe
carries
with
it
a
mandatory
life
sentence,
which
is
now
the
most
severe
sentence
that
English
criminal
law
can
impose
on
an
individual
following
the
1965
abolition
of
the
death penalty.
20
Manslaughter,
on
the
other
hand,
covers
a
large
range
of
different
crimes
of
varying
culpability.
21
There
are
several different
ways
an
individual
can
be
found
guilty
of
manslaughter
under
English
law,
but
for
the
purposes
of
the
upcoming
discussion,
this
Note
will
separate
these
groups
into
three
distinct
types:
manslaughter
by
way
of
a
partial
defense
to
murder;
manslaughter
by
unlawful
and
dangerous
act;
and
manslaughter
by
gross
negligence.
2 2
The
first
is
commonly
referred
to
as
"voluntary
manslaughter,"
while
the
latter
two
are
termed
"involuntary
manslaughter."
Considering
the
different
levels
of
culpability
involved
in
these
distinct
fact
patterns,
judges
are
given
significant
discretion
in
sentencing.
2
3
Manslaughter
by
unlawful
and
dangerous
act
is
also
referred
to
as constructive
manslaughter.
24
It
refers
to
death
that
is
caused
by
the
commission
of
any
crime
that
can
be
considered
"dangerous."
25
The
unlawful
and
dangerous
act
in
question
must
be one
that
merits
criminal,
not
civil,
liability.
26
However,
there
is
no
requirement
that
the
unlawful
and
dangerous
act
be
directed
at
a
person
or
persons.
27
An
act
is
considered
dangerous
if it
is
one
that
all
sober
and
reasonable
people
would
inevitably
recognize
must
subject
the
other
person
to
at
least
the
risk
of
some
harm.
28
This
manslaughter
charge
is
one
that
is
heavily
based
on
constructive
liability-referring
to
when
a crime
has
a
mens
rea
that
only
partially
corresponds
to
the
actus
reus.
This
means
that
a
person
may
be
liable
for
any
death
that
20.
ASHWORTH,
supra
note
15,
at
241,
250;
Murder
(Abolition
of
Death
Penalty)
Act
1965,
c.71,
§
1
(Eng.).
21.
METRO.
POLICE
SENTENCING
COUNCIL,
SENTENCING
FOR
MANSLAUGHTER
1
(n.d.),
https://www.sentencingcouncil.org.uk/wp-content/
uploads/FINAL-Manslaughter-sentencing-leaflet-for-webl.pdf
[https://perma.cc/
W9KB-WYMB].
22.
ASHWORTH,
supra
note
15,
at
273-79.
23. METRO.
POLICE
SENTENCING
COUNCIL,
supra
note
21,
at
1-2.
24.
"Constructive
manslaughter"
is
the
phrase
used
in
DPP
v.
Newbury
(1977)
AC
500,
502-03
(Eng.);
Mitchell
C.
Davies,
Constructive
Manslaughter-A
Not
So
Basic,
Basic
Intent
Crime,
58
J.
CRIM.
L.
398,
398-402
(1994).
25.
With
the
exception
of
strict
liability
crimes;
see
Andrews
v.
Dir.
of
Pub.
Prosecutions
(1937)
AC
576
(Eng.).
26.
R
v.
Franklin
(1883)
15
Cox
CC
163
at
165
(Eng.).
27.
R
v.
Goodfellow
(1986)
83
Crim.
App.
23
at
27
(Eng.).
28.
R
v.
Church
(1966)
1
QB
59
at
60
(Eng.).
2018]
377
COLUMBIA
HUMAN
RIGHTS
LAW
REVIEW
results
from
the
commission
of a
criminal
act,
provided
that
it
is
objectively
dangerous,
even
if
the
person
does
not
foresee
that
any
serious
harm
would
occur.
Academics
have suggested
that
the
rationale
behind
this apparent harshness
is
that
if
a
person
commits
an aggressive
act, she
should
be
fully
liable
for
the
consequences,
as
an
"irrevocable
evil"
has
occurred
if
her
aggressive
act
caused
death.
29
Murder
by
gross
negligence
is
a
variety
of
manslaughter
established
in
the
nineteenth
century
that
is
rather
exceptional
in
that
it
criminalizes
the
causation
of
death
by
an
action
or
omission
that
grossly
fails
to
reach
the
standard
of
a
reasonable
person,
regardless
of
whether
the
individual
in question
is capable
of
reaching
such
a
standard."o
The
elements
for
gross
negligence
manslaughter
are:
(1)
the
defendant
breached
her
of
duty
of
care
towards
the
victim,
(2)
the
breach
of
duty
caused
the death
of
the
victim,
and
(3)
this
breach
of
duty
was
so
"gross"
as
to
merit
criminal
liability.
3 1
The
last
element
is
largely
left
to
the
jury,
but
the
Corporate
Manslaughter
and Corporate
Homicide
Act
of
2007
offers
a
loose
guideline,
defining
it
as
behavior
which falls
"far
below"
what
could
reasonably
be
expected
in
the
circumstances.
3 2
This charge
is
particularly
unique
as
it
can be
satisfied
with
a
mens rea
that
does
address
the
subjective
intention
or
recklessness
of
the
defendant,
but
simply
whether
the
defendant
acted
in
a
way
that
was
reasonable.
33
B.
Self-Defense:
A
General
Defense
to
Homicide
The
doctrine
of
self-defense
at
common
law in
England
and
Wales
removes
the
culpability
of
a person
who
has
to
use
otherwise
criminal
force
either
to
defend
himself
from
an
attack
or
to
prevent
the
commission
of
another
crime.
34
The
defense
is
also
available
to
a
29.
JONATHAN
HERRING,
CRIMINAL
LAW:
TEXTS,
CASES
AND
MATERIALS
292
(6th
ed. 2014).
30.
ASHWORTH,
supra
note
15,
at
273-79;
R
v.
Adomako
et
al. (1995)
1
AC
171,
171
(Eng.);
see
also
R
v.
Finney
(1874)
12
Cox
CC
625, 625
(using
a
test
of
gross
negligence where
an
attendant
at
a
mental
hospital
caused
the
death
of
a
patient
by
releasing
a
flow
of
boiling
water
into
a
bath);
R
v.
Bateman
(1925)
19
Cr
App
R
8,
8
(doctor's
causing
the
death
of
a
woman
was
assessed
to
the
standard
involving
"such
disregard
for
the
life
and
safety
of
others").
31.
POSITIVE
OBLIGATIONS,
supra
note
14,
at
277.
32.
THE
UNION
FOR
PEOPLE
IN
TRANSPORT
AND
TRAVEL,
GROSS
NEGLIGENCE
MANSLAUGHTER
2
(2013),
https://www.tssa.org.uk/download.cfm?
docid=6ED401FA-A5AE-4795-8EF637E78CAEE204
[https://perma.cc/V48S-
MCE31.
33.
R
v.
Adomako
et
al.
(1995)
1
AC
171,
175
(Eng.).
34. R
v.
Williams (Gladstone)
[1987]
3
All
ER
411,
411
(Eng.).
378
[49.3:1
As
Long
as
They
Honestly
Believe
defendant
who
mistakenly
believes
that
he
is
under
attack
or
is
acting
to
prevent
a
crime."
This
mistake
does
not
have
to
be
reasonable,
provided
that
the
defendant
honestly
believed
that
the
circumstances
constituted
a
threat."
The
only
exception
arises
where
the
mistaken
belief
arose
as
a
result
of
voluntary
intoxication.
This
"honest
belief'
doctrine
was
first
established
in
Regina
v.
Gladstone
Williams,
in
which
Lord
Lane
stated
that
the
reasonableness
of
the
defendant's
belief
is
only
"material
to
the
question
of
whether
the
belief
was
held
by
the
defendant
at
all,"
but
"irrelevant"
as
to
the
defendant's
guilt
or
innocence
if
it
was
in
fact
held.
3
'
This
doctrine
of
self-defense,
originally
formed
by
judge-made
common
law,
was
subsequently
codified
in
Parliamentary
legislation
through
the
Criminal
Justice
and Immigration
Act
of
2008."
Once
the
jury
determines
that
a
defendant
did
hold
an
honest
belief,
he
is
to
be
judged
on
the
facts
as
he
believed
them
to
be,
notwithstanding
that
the
belief
may
be
mistaken
and
regardless
of
the
fact
that
the
mistake
may
not
have
been
reasonable.
With
that
said,
when
a
person
uses
otherwise
criminal
force,
the
force
itself
must
be
deemed
reasonable
and
proportionate
in
light
of
the
threat
that
the
defendant
believed
that
he
faced,
and
the
assessment
of
this
force
is
made
objectively.
4 0
However,
the
Act
also
states
that
if
the
jury
determines
that
the
force
was
used
"honestly
and
instinctively,"
it
constitutes
strong
evidence
that
the
act
was
reasonable.
4 1
Unlike
many
jurisdictions
in
the
United
States,
there
is
currently
no
partial
defense
of
imperfect
self-defense
in
the
United
Kingdom.
42
This
means
that
self-defense
under
English
law
can
only
ever
act
as
a
full
defense
to
all
charges-if
any
requirement
of
the
defense
is
demonstrated
not
to
have
been
met,
the
defense
is
not
available
at
all.
4
3
The
burden
of
proof,
however,
lies
on
the
prosecution
to
adduce
35.
Id.
36.
Id.
37.
Criminal
Justice
and
Immigration
Act
2008,
c.
4,
§
76(5)
(Eng.).
38.
R
v.
Williams
(Gladstone)
[1987]
3
All
ER
411,
415
(Eng.).
39.
Criminal
Justice
and
Immigration
Act
2008,
c.
4,
§
76(5)
(Eng.).
40.
See
POSITIVE
OBLIGATIONS,
supra
note
14,
at
117;
R
v.
Jones
and
Milling
et
al.
[2006]
UKHL
16,
[241,
[2007]
1
AC
136
(appeal
taken
from
Eng.).
41.
Criminal
Justice
and
Immigration
Act
2008,
c.
4,
§
76(7)(b)
(Eng.).
42.
U.S.
jurisdictions
with
imperfect
self-defense
are
California
and
Maryland.
See
People
v.
Humphrey,
921
P.2d
1,
6
(Cal.
1996);
State
v.
Faulkner,
483
A.2d
759,
769
(Md.
1984).
See
also
infra
note
163
(citing
Humphrey
and
Faulkner).
43.
Partial
self-defense
was
discussed
by
the
Law
Commission
in
2004.
See
LAW
COMM'N,
PARTIAL DEFENCES
TO
MURDER:
FINAL
REPORT
(2004),
379
2018]
COLUMBIA
HUMAN
RIGHTS
LAW
REVIEW
sufficient
evidence
to
satisfy
a
twelve-person
jury
beyond
a
reasonable
doubt
that
the
defendant
was
not
acting
in
self-defense.4
The
large amount
of
leeway
given
in
self-defense
doctrine
is
in
stark
contrast
to
the
similar
defense
of
duress
by
threat
or
circumstances.
4
1
When
a
person
commits
a crime
under
duress-such
that
the
person reasonably
anticipates death
or
grievous
bodily
harm
and
takes
a
reasonable
and proportional
action
in
response
to
that
threat-they
may
be
excused
of
the
crime.
4 6
In
contrast
to
Self-
defense, which
only
requires
an
honest
belief,
the
doctrine
of
duress
insists
that
the
belief
must
be
reasonable,
the
action
taken
must
be
reasonable and
proportional,
and,
most
importantly,
a
hypothetical
person
"of
reasonable
firmness"
who
would
have
acted
in
the
same
way
as
the
defendant.
47
Furthermore,
the
courts
have
made
it
clear
in
several
cases
that
the
defense
of
duress
is
not
available
for
murder,
not even
as
a
partial
defense.
48
It
is
also
not
available
to
accomplices
to
murder,
as
seen
in
the
unanimous
House
of
Lords
decision
in
Regina
v.
Howe.
49
Part
II
will
discuss
why
this
distinction
is
unsatisfactory
and
highlights
a
doctrinal
problem
in
self-defense.
C.
The
European
Convention
on
Human
Rights
and
the
European
Union
The
European
Convention
on
Human
Rights is
an
international
treaty
that
came
into
force
in
1953
to
protect
human
rights
and
fundamental
freedoms
in
Europe."
It
established
the
European
Court
of
Human
Rights
in
Strasbourg
(hereafter
referred
to
as
Strasbourg
or
the
Strasbourg
Court),
which
is
the
international
http://www.lawcom.gov.uk/wp-content/uploads/2015/03/1c290_PartialDefences-
toMurder.pdf
[https://perma.ce/4EVF-M39Z].
44.
Self-Defence:
Legal
Guidance,
CROWN
PROSECUTION
SERV.,
https://www.cps.gov.uk/legal/s-tou/self
defence/
[https://perma.cc/9TKZ-CDV8].
45.
See
R
v.
Hasan
(Aytach)
[20051
UKHL
22,
[2005]
2
AC
467
(appeal
taken
from
UK).
46.
See
id.
47.
R
v.
Graham
[1982]
1
W.L.R.
294
(UK);
R
v.
Bowen
[1997]
1
W.L.R.
372,
[1996]
4 All
E.R.
837
(UK).
48.
See
R
v.
Dudley
and Stephens
[18841
14
Q.B.D.
273
(UK);
R
v.
Howe
[1987]
1
AC
417
(UK).
49. R
v.
Howe
[19861
UKHL 4
(UK);
R
v.
Howe
[1987]
1
AC
417
(appeal
taken
from
UK).
50.
Note
that
the
European
Convention
has
no
formal links
to
the
European
Union.
380
[49.3:1
As
Long
as
They
Honestly
Believe
court
responsible
for
ruling
on
cases involving
Convention
rights."
When
an
individual
believes
that
her
Convention
rights
are
violated,
she can
submit
an
application
against
the state
responsible
for
the
violation
to
the
Strasbourg
Court,
although
only
after
exhausting
all
possible
alternative
remedies
within
domestic
courts
and
tribunals.
5 2
The
Strasbourg
Court
will
determine
whether
the
right
has
been
breached
and,
if
so,
the
judgment
runs
against
the
state
itself,
as
the
.ECHR
is
meant
to
bind
the
signatory
parties
and
to confer
rights
to
individuals."
The
remedies
that
the
Strasbourg
Court
usually
employs
are
to
require
the
defendant
state
to
pay
compensation
(also
known
as
"just
satisfaction"),
to
adopt
general
measures
such
as
amendments
to
existing
domestic
legislation,
and
to
adopt
individual
measures
such
as
restitution
or
the
reopening
of
the
proceedings."
1.
Article
2
of
the
European
Convention
Article
2
of
the
European
Convention
protects
the
"right
to
life.""
Its
position
as
the
first
right
guaranteed
by
law
demonstrates
its
importance
as
one
of
the
most
fundamental
provisions
in
the
Convention.
The
crucial
nature
of
this
obligation
has
been
reiterated
several
times
in
cases
brought
before
the
Strasbourg
Court.
56
Article
2
establishes
that
every
natural
person's
right
to
life
shall
be
protected
by
law
and
that
no
one
shall
intentionally
be
deprived
of
life."
There are
only
two
exceptions
to
this
law:
first,
the
deprivation
of
life
as a
result
of
a
capital
sentence
after
conviction
of
a
crime
(Article
2(1)),
and,
second,
the deprivation
of
life
caused
by
the
"use
of
force
which
is
no
more
than
absolutely
necessary"
in
defense
of
a
person
from
unlawful
violence,
to
effect
lawful
arrest
or
to
prevent
the
escape
of
a
person
lawfully
detained,
and
under
lawful
action
for
the
purpose
of
quelling
a
riot
or
insurrection
(Article
2(2)).
51.
McCann
v.
United
Kingdom,
21
Eur.
Ct.
H.R.
97 (1995);
Pretty
v.
United
Kingdom,
2002-III
Eur.
Ct.
H.R.
155.
52.
EUROPEAN
COURT
OF
HUmAN
RIGHTS,
THE
LIFE
OF
AN
APPLICATION,
http://www.echr.coe.int/Documents/Case-processing-ENG.pdf
[https://perma.cc/
Y5YF-WSL5].
53.
COUNCIL
OF EUROPE,
FACTSHEET
XV:
RIGHT
OF
INDIVIDUAL
APPLICATION
TO
THE
EUROPEAN
COURT
OF
HUMAN
RIGHTS
(2017),
https://www.coe.int/en/web/echr-toolkit/le-droit-de-requete-individuelle
[https://perma.cc/CYK8-387N].
54.
Id.
55.
European
Convention,
supra
note
12,
art.
2.
56.
McCann
v.
United
Kingdom,
21
Eur.
Ct.
H.R. 97
(1995);
Hugh
Jordan
v.
United
Kingdom,
1998-III
Eur.
Ct.
H.R.
323.
57.
European
Convention,
supra
note
12,
art.
2.
2018]
381
As
Long
as
They
Honestly
Believe
Ireland.
The
Court
ruled,
by
a
split
vote
of
ten
to
nine,
that
the
United
Kingdom
fell
short
in its
control
and
organization
of
the
operation
and
was
thus
required
to
pay
compensation
to
the
estates
of
the
deceased."
In
this
case,
the
Strasbourg
court
ruled
that
a
state
and
its
agents
do
not breach
Article
2
if
otherwise
criminal
force
was
made
in
self-defense
out
of
an
honest
belief,
though
that
belief
must
be
one
that
is borne
of
"good
reason.""
Subsequently,
the Strasbourg
Court
ruled
in
the
2016
case
of
Armani
Da
Silva
v.
United
Kingdom
that
the
existence
of
"good
reasons"
for
the
purpose
of
determining
if
self-defense
can
be
granted
as
an
affirmative
defense
should
be
determined purely
by
assessing
the
subjective
belief
of
the defendant.
6
'
This
case,
where
police
officers
who
shot
an
innocent
man
after
mistaking
him
for
a
suspected
terrorist
even
though
he
did
not
resist
orders,
appears
to
be
a
regression
of
the
McCann
determination."
The
Strasbourg
Court
did
not
recognize
it
as
such
and
simply
referred
to
it
as
an
application
of
the
objective
McCann
test.
Strasbourg
subsequently
concluded
that
there
was
no
violation
of
Article
2,
as
the
officers
had
fulfilled
the
self-defense
requirements
in
U.K.
domestic
law.
However,
Strasbourg
did
not
consider
whether
the
U.K.
domestic
law
was
deficient
in protecting
the
right
to
life,
in
breach
of
the
United
Kingdom's
positive
obligations
to
adopt
a
more
rigorous
set
of
self-
defense
laws
that
sufficiently
and
efficiently
protects
the
right
to
life
of
innocent
victims
of
fatal
attacks
by
perpetrators
who
honestly
and
unreasonably
believed
that
they
were
facing
a
threat
to
their
person.
This
decision
will
be
analyzed
further
in
Part
III.
2.
Human
Rights
Act
As
seen
in
the
previous
section,
an
application
may
be
brought
to
the
Strasbourg
Court.
The
United
Kingdom,
however,
has
another
method
for
an
individual
to
assert
their
Convention
rights
before
a court.
The
Human
Rights
Act,
an
Act
of
Parliament
passed
in
66.
Id.
1
55-56.
67.
ASHWORTH,
supra
note
15,
at
125;
McCann
v.
United
Kingdom,
21
Eur.
Ct. H.R.
97,
1
200
(1995).
68.
Jan
Hessbruegge,
ECtHR
Armani
Da
Silva
v
UK:
Unreasonable
Police
Killings
in
Putative
Self-Defence?,
EJIL:TALK!
(Apr.
14,
2016),
http://www.ejiltalk.org/ecthr-armani-da-silva-v-uk-unreasonable-police-killings-
in-putative-self-defence
[https://perma.cc/C38A-JVGG1
(last
visited
Feb.
26,
2018).
69.
Armani
Da
Silva
v.
United
Kingdom,
App.
No.
5878/08,
248
(Eur.
Ct.
H.R.
Mar.
30,
2016),
available
at
https://www.echr.coe.int.
70.
Id.
2018]
383
COLUMBIA
HUMAN
RIGHTS
LAW
REVIEW
1998,
incorporates
the
ECHR
into
U.K.
law
and
permits
individuals
to
obtain
remedies
from
public
bodies
for
the
breach
of
Convention
rights."
Therefore,
the
Act
brings
into
domestic
legislation
the rights
and
fundamental
freedoms
set
out
in
Articles
2
to
12
and
14
of
the
Convention,
as
well
as
other
protocols
to
the
Convention
ratified
by
the
United
Kingdom.
72
It
obliges
domestic
courts
to
interpret
Convention
rights
in
light
of
the interpretations
that
Strasbourg
has
announced,
and
to
interpret
all
primary
and
secondary legislation
in
a
way
that
is
compatible
with
Convention
rights."
However,
if
and
where
primary
legislation,
which
refers
solely to
an
Act
of
Parliament,
conflicts
with
Convention
rights
so
extensively
that
the
two
cannot
be
reconciled,
domestic
courts
are
required
to
enforce
the
conflicting
primary
legislation
instead,
on
the
principle
of
Parliamentary
sovereignty
that
an
Act
of
Parliament
is
the
highest
form
of
law
in
England
and
Wales.
4
In
such
a
situation,
domestic
courts
still
have
the
power
to
issue
a
declaration
of
incompatibility
to
announce
that
such
a
conflict
has
been
found."
Although
this
Declaration
has
no
legally
binding
power,
it
can
serve as a
strong
political
motivation
for
Parliament
to
resolve
that
incompatibility."
The
Act
also
states
that
the
acts
of
public
authorities
are
to
be
constituted
as
unlawful
if
they
were
performed
in
a
manner
incompatible
with
a
Convention
right.
There
are
two
exceptions,
however:
If
there
is
primary
legislation
which
is
incompatible
with
Convention
rights
that
commands
the authority
to
act
in
a
way
that
violates
that
right,
or
if
there
is
no
other
way
to
enforce
a
provision
of
primary
legislation
that
does
not
violate
Convention
rights,
the
authority's
action
will
not
be
constituted
as
unlawful
under
the
Human
Rights
Act."
3.
European
Union
Charter
of
Fundamental
Rights
The
United
Kingdom,
as
a
Member
State
of
the
European
Union
(EU),
is
ipso
facto
party
to
the
EU
Charter
of
Fundamental
71.
DEP'T
FOR
CONST.
AFF.,
A
Guide
to
the
Human
Rights
Act
1998:
Questions
and
Answers,
5
(Oct.
2006),
http://webarchive.nationalarchives.gov.uk/
+/http:/www.dca.gov.uk/peoples-rights/human-rights/pdflact-studyguide.pdf
[https://perma.cc/8GDG-UL53]
(last
visited
Feb.
26, 2018).
72.
Human
Rights
Act
1998,
c.
42,
§
1(1)(a)
(UK).
73.
Id.
§§
2-3.
74.
Id.
§
3(2).
75.
Id.
§
4.
76.
Id.
77.
Id.
§
6.
384
[49.3:1
As
Long
as
They
Honestly
Believe
Rights
(EU
Charter)."
The
EU
Charter
became
binding
on
all
EU
institutions
and
member
states
in
2009,
and
includes
all
the
rights
and
freedoms
enshrined
in
the
ECHR,
rights
found
in
the
case
law
of
the
Court
of
Justice
of
the
European
Union,
and
other
rights
and
principles
arising
from
the
common
constitutional
traditions
of
EU
member
states.
9
While
the
rights
included
in
the
EU
Charter
are
consistent
with those
in the
ECHR
and
are
of
equivalent
scale
and
scope,
the
EU
Charter
applies
only
when
EU
member
states
adopt
national
law
for
the
purpose
of
implementing
an
EU
directive,
or
when
national
authorities
apply
an
EU
regulation
directly.o
Therefore,
as
current
U.K.
self-defense
law
is
based
entirely
on
the
common
law
and
Parliamentary
legislation
that
is
unrelated
to
any
EU
regulation
or
directive,
the
Charter
should
not
apply."
However,
while
the
European
Union cannot
adopt
a
general
criminal
code
that
applies
throughout
the
Union,
it
is
possible
for
the
European
Union
to
adopt
a
directive
requiring
member
states
to
adopt
a
minimum
standard
on
the
definition
of
criminal
offences.
82
In
such
a
case,
if
the
member
state
fails
to
implement
the
directive
or
implements
it
insufficiently,
it
can
face
liability
in
suits brought
by
the
European
Union
itself."
Individuals
who
have
suffered
a
loss
or
whose
rights
have been
infringed
by
the
failure
to
implement
the
directive can
also
bring
suit
through the
principle
of
state
liability
established
in
Francovich
v.
Italy,
as
long
as the
individual
can
prove
that
the
directive
conferred
specific
rights
upon
individuals
and
that
there
is
a
causal
link
between
the
state's
failure
to
implement
the
directive
and the
loss
suffered.
84
In
light
of
the
results
of
the
EU
Referendum
in
2016,
where
the
popular
vote
reflected
the
majority's
desire
for
the
United
Kingdom to
leave
the
European
Union,
the
United
Kingdom's
78.
EU
member
countries
in
brief,
EUROPA,
https://europa.eu/european-
union/about-eu/countries/member-countries-en
[https://perma.cc/YPD5-HRD9}
(last
visited
Feb.
3,
2018).
79.
Charter
of
Fundamental
Rights
of
the
European
Union,
Oct.
26,
2012,
2012
O.J.
(C
326),
http://eur-lex.europa.eullegal-content/EN/TXT/?uri=
CELEX:12012P/TXT
[https://perma.cc/ZM7F-9SAN]
[hereinafter
Charter
of
Fundamental
Rights].
80.
Id.
at
tit.
VII.
81.
Id.
82.
Id.
83.
EU
Acts
Against
Member
States
for
Failure
to
Implement
Directives,
OUT-LAW.COM
(Jan.
7,
2003),
http://www.out-law.com/page-3218
[https://perma.cc/
74S3-K89Y];
Case
C-6/90,
Francovich
v.
Italy,
1991
E.C.R.
1-5375.
84.
Case
C-6/90,
Francovich
v.
Italy,
1991
E.C.R.
1-5375.
2018]1
385
COLUMBIA
HUMAN
RIGHTS
LAW
REVIEW
departure
from
the
European
Union
appears
to
be
inevitable."
Thus,
the
EU
Charter
can
no
longer
be
a
valid method
of
influencing
changes
in
English
self-defense
laws.
Despite
that,
the
European
Union's
recognition
and
incorporation
of
ECHR
standards
does
in
fact
demonstrate
European
countries'
general
respect
for ECHR
rights.
II.
PROBLEMS
The
current
doctrine
of
English
self-defense
law
is
problematic
for
several
reasons,
particularly
in
that
its
requirement
of
"honest belief'
has
left
many
cases
of
police
brutality,
sometimes
even
resulting
in
fatalities,
unprosecuted
and
unchecked.
On
a
doctrinal
level,
this
Note
finds
the
current
law
to
be
lacking
in
legal
certainty
and
fairness.
It
is also
arguably
contrary
to
the
United
Kingdom's obligations
under
the
ECHR,
though
the
Strasbourg
Court
has
so
far
failed
to
require
any
change
in
English
law.
A.
"Honest
Belief' and
Police
Brutality
The
cases
of
Sharman
and
Bennett
described
in
the
introduction
are far
from
the
only
cases
in
which
police
officers
escaped
criminal liability
for
acts
of
violence
against
innocent
citizens
on
the
basis
of self-defense.
86
The
fact
that
English
law
does
not
require
an examination
of
the
reasonableness
of
an
officer's
belief,
as
long
as
it
is
"honest,"
has
also
left
many
cases
of
police
brutality
to
be
unprosecuted.
In
2005,
Jean
Charles
de
Menezes
was
fatally shot
in
the
London
Underground
when
the
police
mistook
him
for
a
suspected
suicide
bomber."
The
Crown
Prosecution
Service
did
not
prosecute
the
officers
even
though
the
Independent
Police
Complaints
Commission
(IPCC) recognized
that
the
mistake
made
was
arguably
unreasonable,
as
the
standard
of
"reasonable
force"
is
assessed
in
85.
Alex
Hunt
&
Brian
Wheeler,
Brexit:
All
you
need
to
know
about
the
UK
leaving
the
EU,
BBC
NEWS
(Jan..30,
2018),
http://www.bbc.com/news/uk-politics-
32810887
[https://perma.cc/2VVS-U9GK].
86.
See
R
(on
the
application
of
Sharman)
v.
HM
Coroner
for
Inner
North
London
[2005]
EWCA
(Civ) 967
[1]-[9],
[20051
Inquest
L.R.
168
(Eng.);
R
(on
the
application
of
Bennett)
v.
HM
Coroner
for
Inner
South
London
[20071
EWCA
(Civ)
617
[351-[36],
[2007]
Inquest
L.R. 163
(Eng.).
87.
JOHANNES
KEILER
&
DAVID
ROEF,
COMPARATIVE
CONCEPTS OF
CRIMINAL
LAW
146 (2015)
[hereinafter
COMPARATIVE
CONCEPTS].
386
[49.3:1
As
Long
as
They
Honestly
Believe
accordance
with
the
"honest
belief'
of
the
defendant,
regardless
of
how
unreasonable
that
belief
may
be."
The
"honest
belief'
doctrine
in
the
United
Kingdom
is
exceptional.
Many
other
states
with
long-established
criminal
legal
systems,
including
those
that
were
previous
British
colonies
and
whose
laws
derived
significant
inspiration
from
the
English
law,
require
that
a
mistaken
belief
must
be
reasonable
for
the
purposes
of
self-defense.
For
instance,
the
general
rule
in
the
United
States
is
that
a
person
is only
entitled
to
use
force
for
the
purpose
of
self-
defense
if
it
reasonably
appears
necessary
to
defend
herself
against
an
unlawful
and
immediate
threat
of
violence."
When
the
use
of
force
is
fatal,
the
law
more
strictly
requires
a
reasonable
belief
that
force
is
required
to
prevent
the
infliction
of
grievous
bodily
harm
or
death."
Similarly,
Singaporean
law
requires
that
one
must
reasonably
apprehend
death
or
grievous
hurt
in
an
assault
to
justify
the
use
of
deadly
force
in
self-defense."
Many
other
countries
in
Europe
also
require
a
standard
of
reasonable
belief.
For
example,
French
law
requires
the
defendant
to
have
an
honest
and
reasonable
belief
that
an
imminent
threat
exists.
9 2
The
Strasbourg
Court,
through
the
case
of
McCann,
has
also
ruled
that
police
officers
may
only
open
fire
against
a
person
if
they
have
reasonable
grounds
for
believing
that
he
or
she
is
committing
or
about
to
commit
an
act
which
would
endanger
their
lives
or
the
lives
of
innocents
and
that
the
use
of
force
is
absolutely
necessary."
German
law
is
slightly
less
certain:
A
strict
textual
interpretation
of
the
German
Criminal
Code
section
32,
which
states
that
self-defense
88.
Criminal
Justice
and
Immigration
Act
2008,
c.
4,
§
76
(Eng.);
COMPARATIVE
CONCEPTS,
supra
note
87,
at
146;
Armani
Da
Silva
v. U.K.,
App.
No.
5878/08,
1
251
(Eur.
Ct.
H.R.
Mar.
30,
2016),
available
at
https://www.echr.coe.int.
89.
GEORGE
E.
DIX, GILBERT
LAW
SUMMARIES:
CRIMINAL
LAW
XXXIII
(18th
ed.
2010);
see
generally
DAVID
C.
BRODY
&
JAMES
R.
ACKER,
CRIMINAL
LAW
(2014)
(outlining
the
general
approach
to
the
self-defense
defense
in
the
United
States).
90.
RANETA
LAWSON
MACK,
A
LAYPERSON'S
GUIDE
TO
CRIMINAL
LAW
141
(1999).
91.
What
Can
I
do
to
Protect
Myself
in
Self-Defence
in
Singapore?,
SING.
LEGAL
ADVICE,
https://singaporelegaladvice.com/1aw-articles/what-can-i-do-to-
protect-myself-in-self-defence-in-singapore/
[https://perma.cc/5BTZ-APC9]
(last
visited
Feb.
3,
2018);
see
also
SING.
PEN.
CODE
§§
96-106
(providing
Singapore's
statutory
provisions
concerning
the
"[r]ight
of
private
defence").
92.
See
Kenneth
W.
Simons,
Self
Defense:
Reasonable
Beliefs
or
Reasonable
Self-Control?,
11
NEW
CRIM.
L.
REV.
51, 53
n.2.
93.
McCann
v.
United
Kingdom,
21
Eur.
Ct. H.R.
97
(1995).
387
2018]
COLUMBIA
HUMAN
RIGHTS
LAW
REVIEW
"means
any
defensive
action
that
is
necessary
to
avert
an
imminent
unlawful
attack,"
would
mean
that
the
threat
must
be
genuine
and
no
mistaken
belief,
even
a
reasonable
one,
will
avail
the
private
defense.
94
However,
German
self-defense
law
is
known
to
be
lenient
when
it
comes
to
the
force
used in response
to
the threat,
and
the
force
used
in
self-defense is
only
unjustifiable
when
it
is
grossly
disproportionate
to
the
threat.
9 5
It
is
still
unclear whether
German
law
would accept
a
mistaken
belief
as sufficient
grounds
for
self-
defense."
Though,
given
the
explicit
distinction
between
justifications
and
excuses
in
German
law,
mistaken
belief
would
likely
be
categorized
as
the
latter.
97
Nonetheless,
it
appears
that
the
English
position
of accepting
mistaken
beliefs
as
long
as
they
are
honestly
perceived
is
an
exceptional
one.
Arguably
English
law
has
been
reluctant
to
extend
the
requirement
of
reasonable
belief
for self-defense
beyond
the
realm
of
civil
lawsuits
as
it
recognizes
a
need
to
separate
criminal
culpability
from
civil
liability.
98
Civil
liability
is
frequently
grounded
in
negligence,
whereas
it
is
much
less
common
for
negligence,
no
matter
how
extensive,
to
form
the
basis
of
criminal
liability."
For
one
to
be
culpable
of
a criminal
offense,
there
is
the
notion
that
one
must
have
performed
a
"morally
undesirable"
act,
and
that
the
defendant
performing
that
act,
not
just
the
act itself,
is especially
blameworthy.o
In English
law,
the
idea
of
criminal
culpability
as
a
form
of
moral
assessment
is
particularly
prevalent;
culpability
thus
requires
that
the
defendant,
in performing
an
act,
disclose
some
"shortfall
of
character"
or
"deficiency
of
virtue.""
0
'
Hence,
a
person's
actions
may
be
undesirable
to
others
or
to
society
as
a
whole,
but
that
does
not
mean
a person
is
necessarily
culpable
where
the
action
taken
does
not
reflect
poor
moral
character
on
his
part.
10
2
However,
the
person
may
still
be
liable
in a
civil
case
out
of
the
simple
reason
that
94.
COMPARATIVE
CONCEPTS,
supra
note
87,
at
136.
95.
Simons,
supra
note
92,
at
53.
96.
Id.
97.
Miriam
Gur-Arye,
Should
a
Criminal
Code
Distinguish
Between
Justification and
Excuse?,
5
CAN.
J.L.
&
JURIS.
215,
215
(1992).
98.
For
a
discussion
of
culpability,
see
DENNIs
J.
BAKER
&
JEREMY
HORDER,
SANCTITY
OF
LIFE
AND
THE CRIMINAL
LAW:
THE
LEGACY OF GLANVILLE
WILLIAMS
178
(2015)
[hereinafter
SANCTITY
OF
LIFE].
99.
GLANVILLE
WILLIAMS, TEXTBOOK
CRIMINAL
LAW
91
(London:
Stevens
&
Son.
ed.,
2d
ed. 1983).
100.
SANCTITY
OF
LIFE,
supra
note
98,
at
179.
101.
Id.
at
180.
102.
Id.
388
[49.3:1
As
Long
as
They
Honestly
Believe
her
actions
are
undesirable.
In
the
case
of
English
self-defense
law,
the
difference
is
drawn
in
that
a
person
is
civilly
liable
in
tort
if
he
makes
an
honest
but
unreasonable
mistake
and
uses
force
upon
another
as
a
result
of
it
(as
seen in
Ashley
v.
Chief
Constable),
but
he
is
not
criminally
culpable.'o
His act
of
unreasonably
harming
another
person
is
not
blameworthy,
but
it
is
socially
undesirable.
A
discussion
of
the
doctrinal
bases
of
drawing
such
a
difference
can
be
found
in
Ashley
v.
Chief
Constable.
10
4
In
Ashley,
the
House
of
Lords
held
that
self-defense
to
a civil
claim
for
tortious
assault
and
battery,
where
the
assailant
had
acted
in
the
mistaken
belief
that
he
was
in
imminent
danger
of
being
attacked,
required
that
such a
mistaken
belief
must
be
honestly
and
reasonably
held.
Lord
Scott,
speaking
for
the
majority,
stated
that
as
the
function
of
the
civil
law
of
tort
is
different
from
that
of
the
criminal
law,
the
standard
for
one's
state
of
mind
in
self-defense
should
differ.'
0 5
Where
the
main
function
of
criminal
law
is
to
"identify,
and
provide
punitive
sanctions
for"
behavior
that
is
categorized
as
criminal
because
it
is
"damaging
to
the
good
order
of society,"
the
function
of
tort
law
is
to
"identify
and
protect
the
rights"
of
people,
and
to
balance
between
these
rights.'o
According
to
Lord
Scott
in
Ashley,
this
distinction
explains
the
difference
in
the
elements
of
self-defense
in
criminal
and
tort
law.
This
Note,
however,
finds
flaws
with
this
explanation.
While
it
is
understandable
that
the English
courts
would
want
draw
such
a
distinction,
it
is
still
problematic
for
many
reasons.
For
one,
the
doctrinal
basis
of
drawing
such
a
formalistic
distinction
between
self-defense
in
criminal
law
and
self-defense
in
tort
law
based
on
an
almost
artificial
notion
is
regrettable.
While
such
a
difference
does
exist,
it
is
merely
a
guideline
and
should
not
be
formed
in
absolutes.
As
a
matter
of
fact,
Lord
Scott's
explanation
is
not
consistent
with
many
English
legal
doctrines.
Many
doctrines
in
English
criminal
law
are
in fact
meant
to
"identify
and protect
the
rights"
of
people
through
a
deterrent
effect.o'
One
such example
103.
Ashley
v.
Chief
Constable
of
Sussex
Police
[20081
UKHL
25
(appeal
taken
from
Eng.).
104.
Id.
at
96.
105.
Id.
106.
Id.
107.
Id.
(arguing
that
the
main
function
of
the
civil
law
of
tort
"is
to
identify
and
protect
the
rights
that
every
person
is
entitled
to
assert
against,
and
require
to
be
respected
by,
others.
The
rights
of
one
person,
however,
often
run
counter
to
the
rights
of
others
and
.
. .
the
law
of
tort[]
must
then
strike
a
balance
between
the
conflicting
rights.").
389
2018]
COLUMBIA
HUMAN
RIGHTS
LAW
REVIEW
would
be
the
doctrine
of gross
negligence
manslaughter,
which
brings
the
ordinarily
tortious
concept-
breach
of
one's
duty
of
care-into
the
criminal
sphere
for
the
policy-based
purpose
of
upholding individuals'
responsibility
for
the
health
and
safety
of
others.
108
The
purpose
of
protecting individual
rights
is
not
exclusive
to
civil
law.
The
existence of gross
negligence
manslaughter
shows
that
English
law
does
recognize
that
the
criminalization
of
certain
forms
of
unreasonable
conduct
is
crucial
to
protect individual rights.
The
influential
criminal
law
scholar,
Glanville
Williams,
also
acknowledged
in
1983
that
even
though
there
is
significant
moral
difficulty
in
punishing
people
for
what
they
cannot
help,
negligence
is
still
an
appropriate
ground
of
moral
reproach.'
In
fact,
criminal
defenses
especially
are
inextricably
concerned
with
a
balancing
of
rights
between
the
perpetrator
and the
victim,
and
English
judges
have
also recognized
this
concern in
self-defense
cases
involving
mistaken
beliefs
arising
from
voluntary
intoxication.`
0
Therefore,
this
artificial distinction
is
neither
explainable
nor desirable.
Lord
Scott's
reasoning
also
appears
weak as
a
matter
of
principle.
Lord
Scott
has
recognized
it
himself,
in
Ashley,
that
the
purpose
of
criminal
law
is
to
punish
actions
that
are
"damaging
to
the
good
order
of
society.""'
In
stating
so,
he
separates
the
purpose
of
criminal
law
from
the
civil
law
of
tort,
which is
meant
to
balance
between
the
rights
of individuals.
11 2
However,
there
is
little
explanation
as
to
how
acting
on
a
grossly
unreasonable
belief in
attacking
an
innocent
and
not
facing
a
criminal
penalty
is not
"damaging
to
the
good
order
of
society."
There
is
simply
no
explanation
as
to
why
English
courts,
and the
legislature,
are
so
unwilling
to
assess the reasonableness
of a
defendant's
belief
at
all
in
the
defendant's
use
of
force
against
another
person,
when
such
a
belief
can
constitute
an
incredibly
significant
aspect
of
the
defendant's justification
or
excuse
in a
case
where
he
has
mistakenly
thought
he
was
under
an imminent
threat.
As
a
result,
as
has
already
been
asserted,
many cases
of
police
officers
using
deadly
force
against
innocents
are
simply
not
prosecuted,
or
summarily
dismissed,
with
little
examination
into
the
reasonableness
of
the
police
officer's
beliefs.
108.
THE
UNION
FOR
PEOPLE
IN
TRANSPORT
AND
TRAVEL,
supra
note
32,
at
3.
109.
WILLIAMS,
supra
note
99.
110.
Regina
v.
O'Connor
[1991]
Crim.
L.R.
135
(Eng.).
111.
[2008]
1
AC
962,
[17].
112.
Ashley
v.
Chief
Constable
of
Sussex
Police
[2008]
UKHL
25
(Eng.).
390
[49.3:1
As
Long
as
They
Honestly
Believe
This
is
concerning
as
police
officers
are
by
nature
capable
of
wielding
a
drastic
amount
of
force
against
civilians.
It
is
thus
crucial
that
this
amount
of
capacity
be
justified.
Police
brutality
on
the
basis
of
racial
bias
is
especially
concerning,
and
there
is
a
disturbing
trend
of
law
enforcement
officers
viewing
black
citizens
in
particular
as
inherently
threatening.
1
More
black
people
are
jailed
in
England
and
Wales
proportionally
than
in
the
United
States
as
of
2010.114
Black
people
make
up
fifteen
percent
of
the
prison
population
in
the
United
Kingdom,
even
though
they
constitute
only
2.2
percent
of
the
general
population.
1 5
Police
discrimination
and
violence
against
black
people
are
also
common
in
the United
Kingdom.
1
There
is
an
immense
amount
of
evidence
demonstrating
that
police
racism
commonly
results
in
deaths
of
innocent black
men
and
women
who
were
seen
as
threatening
simply
by
virtue
of
their
race,
though
such
incidents
are
more
commonly
reported
in
the
United
States
than
the
United Kingdom."'
Arguably,
the
only
way
to
work
to
overcome
this
is
to
insist
that
unreasonable
beliefs
should
no
longer
be
tolerated
as
an
excuse
that
avails
an
attacker,
who
intentionally
harmed
or
even
killed
an innocent
person
on
the
basis
of
a
racist
belief,
to
a
defense
that
rids
him
completely
of
any
culpability.
B.
Unreasonable
Beliefs
and
Manslaughter
Another
major
problem
in
English
self-defense
law,
in
cases
where
a
mistaken
but
genuine belief
has
resulted
in
the
defendant's
use
of
fatal
force
against
the
victim,
arises
from
the
fact
that
self-
defense is
available
in
its
current
form
to
all
forms
of
homicide
in
a
way
that
subverts
the
purpose
of
some
homicide
laws
in
the
first
113.
Randeep Ramesh,
More
Black
People
Jailed
in
England
and
Wales
Proportionally
than
in
US,
GUARDIAN
(Oct.
10,
2010),
https://www.theguardian.com/society/2010/oct/11/black-prison-population-
increase-england
[https://perma.cc/6GWJ-JZV5].
114.
Id.
115.
Id.
116.
Siana
Bangura,
We
Need
to
Talk
About
Police
Brutality
in
the
U.K.,
FADER
(Mar.
29,
2016),
http://www.thefader.com/2016/03/29/police-brutality-uk-
essay
[https://perma.cc/CB2M-P933].
117.
Id.
("The
U.K.
has
a
long
history
of
state
violence,
however,
compared
to
the
U.S.
there
is
much
less
visibility
of
this
in
mainstream
media.").
See
generally
Daniel
Funke
&
Tina
Susman,
From
Ferguson
to
Baton
Rouge:
Deaths
of
Black
Men
and
Women
at
the
Hands
of
Police,
L.A.
TIMES
(July
12,
2016),
http://www.latimes.comination/la-na-police-deaths-20160707-snap-htmlstory.html
(on
file
with
the Columbia
Human
Rights
Law
Review)
(cataloguing
murders
of
black
men
and
women
by
police
officers).
2018]
391
As
Long
as
They
Honestly
Believe
contrary
to
the
standard
of
a
reasonable
person
that
it results
in
the
death
of
another
person.
Manslaughter
by
gross
negligence
is
predicated
on
the
idea
that
the
defendant's
course
of
conduct
was
grossly
unreasonable,
caused
death,
and
she
should
hence
be
culpable
for
it.
With
that
in
mind,
it
is
very
odd
that
English
self-defense
can
excuse
this
type
of
manslaughter,
meaning
that
a
defendant
can
be
fully
acquitted
of
gross
negligence
manslaughter
when
his
grossly
unreasonable-but
genuine-belief
had
caused
death.
This
leads
to
the absurd
result
that
the
elements
that
could
prove
a
conviction
of
gross
negligence
manslaughter
would
instead
prove
the
existence
of
self-defense
acquitting
a
defendant
of
gross
negligence
manslaughter.
It
cannot
be
explained
why
a crime
that
specifically
punishes
a
person
for
taking
a completely
unreasonable
action can
allow
a
full
defense
that
is
based
on
a
completely
unreasonable
action.
It
bars
the
ability
of
the
court
to
assess
the
reasonableness
of
the
very
basis
of
a
potentially
unjustified
action
that
a
person
has
taken
which
has
caused
the
death
of
another.
As
an
illustration,
we
can
examine
the
case
of
Regina
v.
Adomako
in
comparison
with
the
cases
of
police
brutality
previously
mentioned.
In
Adomako,
an
anesthetist's
conviction
of
manslaughter
by
gross
negligence
was
upheld
on
the
basis
that
he
had
caused
a
patient's
death
by
failing
to
notice
a disconnection
in
his
oxygen
pipe,
which
was
a
gross
breach
of
duty
as
it
fell
far
below
the
standard
of
a
reasonable
doctor-which
was
a
much
higher
standard
than
that
of
a
reasonable person.
1 2 4
In
contrast,
the
police
officer
in
Sharman
who
fatally
shot Stanley
on
the
mistaken
belief
that
the
table
leg
he
was
carrying
was
a
shotgun
was
not
even
held
to
the
standard
of
a
reasonable
person,
let
alone
that
of
a
reasonable
trained
police
officer,
in
the
formation
of
that
belief
because
of
the
nature
of
English
self-
defense
law.'
25
Therefore,
even
though
he
had
caused
death
with
an
action
taken
in
what
was
arguably
a
gross
breach
of
his
duty
of
care,
he
cannot
be
convicted
of
gross
negligence
manslaughter,
or
any
other
form
of
homicide.
English
self-defense
law
thus
undermines
the
124.
R
v.
Adomako et.
al.
[1995]
1
A.C.
171
at
188
(Eng.);
Ying
Hui
Tan,
Law
Report:
Anaesthetist's
conviction for
manslaughter
upheld:
Regina
v
Adomako
-
House
of
Lords,
INDEPENDENT
(June
30,
1994),
http://www.independent.co.uk/news/uk/law-report-anaesthetists-conviction-for-
manslaughter-upheld-regina-v-adomako-house-of-lords-lord-1410881.html
[https://perma.cc/AVN7-UVK6].
125.
R
(on
the
application
of
Sharman)
v.
HM
Coroner
for
Inner
North
London
[2005] EWCA
(Civ)
967
[1]-[9],
[20051
Inquest
L.R. 168
(Eng.).
393
2018]
COLUMBIA
HUMAN
RIGHTS
LAW
REVIEW
purpose
of
gross
negligence
manslaughter
entirely,
and generates
results
that
are
noticeably
unfair.
C.
An
Artificial
"Reasonableness"
Element
On
the
discussion
of
the
"honest
belief'
doctrine,
we
must
still
note
that
English
courts
have
not,
in
fact,
completely
dismissed all
honest
beliefs
as
justified.
While
there
is
no
reasonableness
element
in
assessing
whether an
honest
belief
is
justified,
legislation
and
past
case
law
has
established
that
there
is
one
type
of
mistaken
belief
that
cannot
be
justified
as
an
"honest
belief'
that
can
avail
the
defendant
of
the
justification
of
self-defense.
12 6
The
only
situation
in
which
the
"honest
belief'
doctrine
does
not
apply
on
its
face
is
if
the
mistaken
belief
was caused
by
the
intoxication
of
the
defendant
at
the
time
of
the
act,
even
if
that
belief
could
be
considered
reasonable,
provided
that
the
defendant
would
not have
had
that
belief
if
he
were
sober.
127
This
rule
was
codified
in
the
Criminal
Justice
and Immigration
Act
in
2008,
but
its
history
dates
much
longer
than
that.
1
28
While
self-
defense
was
still
a common-law
defense,
several
Court
of
Appeal
cases
have
firmly
held
that
a
defendant's
drunken
belief
can
never
be
relied
on
for
the
purpose
of
self-defense.1
29
In
Regina
v.
O'Grady,
a
case
decided
about
30
years
before
legislative
codification
of
this
doctrine,
Lord
Chief
Justice
Lane
stated
that
the rationale
for
barring
drunken
beliefs
was
to
balance
between
the
"competing
interests"
of
the
defendant
and
the
victim.
He
thus
concluded
that
the
defendant
deserves
a
conviction,
because
the
fault
in
such
a
case
would
lie
mainly
on
the
defendant,
rather
than
the
victim
who
suffered
"through
no
fault
of
his
own"
as
a
result
of
the
defendant's
"drunken
mistake."
13
o
Interestingly
enough,
this
statement
essentially
rejects
the
opinion
of
Lord
Scott
more
than
30
years
later
in
Ashley,
that
the
courts
should
only
balance
interests
between
individuals
when
in
the
realm
of
tort
law.
3
1
Apart
from
the
exclusion
of
situations
involving
voluntary
intoxication,
which
has
been
rooted
in
the
common
law
for
decades
126.
Director
of
Public
Prosecutions
v.
Majewski
[1977]
AC
443,
[1976]
UKHL
2
(appeal
taken
from
Eng.).
127.
Criminal
Justice
and Immigration
Act
2008
c.4,
§
76
(Eng.).
128.
Id.
129.
R
v.
O'Grady
[1987]
1
QB
995
(Eng.);
R
v.
O'Connor
[19911
Crim
LR
135
(Eng.);
R
v.
Hatton
[20061
1
Cr.
App.
R
16
(Eng.).
130.
R
v.
O'Grady
[1987]
1
QB
995
(Eng.).
131.
Ashley
v.
Chief
Constable
of
Sussex
Police
[2008]
UKHL
25,
[18]
(appeal
taken
from Eng.).
394
[49.3:1
As
Long
as
They
Honestly
Believe
and subsequently
expressly
codified
by
legislation,
the
courts
have
recently
also
excluded
beliefs
that
arise
from
a
delusional
state
of
mind.
In
the
2013
case
of
Regina
v.
Oye,
the
defendant
mistakenly
thought,
while
in
a
delusional
state
of
mind,
that
he
was
under
threat
of
attack
by
police
officers.
132
He
perceived
the
officers
as
evil
spirits
and
spontaneously
assaulted
them.as
At
trial, the
Crown
found
that
since
his
belief
was
a
genuine
one
that
did
not
arise
from
voluntary
intoxication
(the
"honest
belief'
requirement
in
§76(4)),
and
the
use
of
force
was
reasonable
in
the
circumstances
as
he
mistakenly
perceived
them
to
be
(the
"reasonable
force"
requirement
in
§76(6)),
he
should
be
acquitted
on
the
basis
of
self-defense.
13 4
The
Court
of
Appeal
reversed
the
decision
on
the
basis
that
an
insane
person
cannot
set
the
standard
of
reasonableness
as
to
the
degree
of
force
used
by
reference
to
his
own
insanity.'
It
added
that
it
would
make
"little
sense"
for
the
jury
to
put
themselves
into
the
shoes
of
a
"reasonable
lunatic."
1
3 6
Therefore,
the
force
used
cannot
possibly
be
"reasonable"
for
the
purposes
of
the
objective
requirement
of
reasonable
force.
In
deciding
the
ruling,
Lord
Justice
Davis
pointed
out
that
the
trial
court's
holding
was
concerning
because
allowing
the
defense
would
mean
"the
more
insanely
deluded
a
person
may
be
in
using
violence
in
purported
self-defence
the
more
likely
that
an
entire
acquittal
may
result."
1 37
This
statement
demonstrates
the
policy
decisions
behind
this
ruling
and
the
idea
that
English
courts
are
still,
to
some
extent,
willing
to
bar
the
defense
to
honest
but
delusional
beliefs,
even
though
it
is
not
stated
in legislation.
138
Furthermore,
while
English
law
employs
a
subjective
test
for
the
defendant's
belief
in
the
existence
of
an
imminent
threat,
it
applies
an
objective
test
for
whether
or
not
the
defendant's
use
of
force
is
reasonable
given
the
belief
that
the
defendant
has
in mind.
139
This
demonstrates
a
certain
awareness
on
part
of
the
legislature
and
judiciary
to
impose
some
form
of
a
reasonableness
element
to
prevent
self-defense
from
being
used
to
completely
absolve
someone
of
culpability
when
he
has
acted
with
grossly
disproportionate
force.
132.
R
v.
Oye
[20131
EWCA
Crim
1725,
[20141
1
W.L.R.
3354,
[2]
(Eng.).
133.
Id.
at
[19].
134.
Id.
at
[46]-[481.
135.
Id.
at
[47].
136.
Id.
137.
Id.
at
[451.
138.
R
v.
Oye
[2013]
EWCA
Crim
1725,
[2014]
1
W.L.R.
3354,
[56]
(Eng.).
139.
Criminal
Justice
and
Immigration
Act
2008,
c.4,
§
76(4)(b)
(Eng.).
395
2018]1
COLUMBIA
HUMAN
RIGHTS
LAW
REVIEW
However,
while
it
is
respectable
that
the
English
law
has
accepted
that
there
ought
to
be
certain
"honest
beliefs" which
are
so
unreasonable
or
unjustified
that
they
cannot
be
relied
on
by
defendants
who
seek
to
plead
self-defense,
and
does
attempt
to
add
a
layer
of
reasonableness
through
the
requirement
"reasonable
force,"
this
Note
finds
that
the
rigid
nature
and
legal
uncertainty
of
these
rules
have
generated
further
problems
for
English
self-defense law.
First,
the
rigid
nature
of
the
two
blanket
exclusions is
unfair
and
neglects
underlying
problems.
These
attempts
to
narrow
the
excessively
broad
nature
of
the
"honest
belief'
doctrine
result
in
the
exclusion
of
drunken
and
deluded
beliefs
on
the basis
that
they
are
automatically
unjustifiable
or
unreasonable.
This
is
simultaneously
over-inclusive
and
under-inclusive.
It
is
under-inclusive
as
it
does
not
include
other
forms
of
unreasonable
beliefs
such
as
racist
beliefs,
or
unreasonable
police
brutality.
It
is over-inclusive
as
it
presumes
that
all
intoxicated
beliefs
are
per
se
unreasonable-for
example,
as
pointed
out
by
Dr.
Jonathan
Rogers,
an
intoxicated
woman
who
is
walking
home
at
night
would
not
be
able
to
plead
self-defense
to
instinctively
pepper-spraying
a
person
whom
she
mistakenly
believed
was
following
her.
14 0
If
we
consider
the
purpose
of
criminal
law
to
deter
the
commission
of
societally
undesirable
acts,
and
also
as
a
method
of
ascribing
moral blame
to someone,
both
are
left
unsatisfied.
It
is
first
unclear,
from
a
Benthamite
perspective
of
criminal
law
as
influencing
societal
behavior,
what
this
is
meant
to
deter.
While one could
say
that
it
is
meant
to
deter
people
from
walking
home
alone
at
night
while
drinking
(which
is
absurd),
or
to
prevent
people
from
acting
on
their
honest
and
instinctive
impulses
to
defend
themselves
against
perceived
threats
when
drunk
(which
negates
the
purpose
of
self-defense
in
the first
place
and
can
cost
people
their
lives),
neither
make
much sense
as a
policy
measure.
There
is also
much
less
moral
blame
we
can
ascribe
to
a
person
who
acts
on
her
impulses
to
defend
herself
when
intoxicated,
compared
to
one
who
makes
automatically
racist
beliefs
when
sober,
but
the
latter
will be
allowed
the
full
defense
and
the
former
nothing.
The
simultaneously
over-inclusive
and under-inclusive
nature
of
the
current
law
results
in a
situation
wherein
an
intoxicated
woman
walking
home would
not
have a
defense
when
she
instinctively
pepper-sprays
a person
whom
she
thought
was
following
her-
whereas
a
person
who
is
naturally
racist
would
get
off
scot-free
as
140.
Jonathan
Rogers,
Let
the
drunkard
lie!,
1555(7204)
NEW
L.J.
1892,
1892-93
(2005).
396
[49.3:1
As
Long
as
They
Honestly
Believe
long
as
he
was
sober,
or
even
if
he
was
drunk
but
would
have
made
the
same
mistake
if
he
were
sober."'
A
greater
concern
arises
where
mistaken
beliefs
are
created
with
little regard
as
to
whether
they
are
true.
Many cases
involving
police
officers
who
have
become
used
to
the
violence
possibly
inherent
in
their
line
of
duty
do
in
fact
create
beliefs
that
individuals
are
about
to
use
violence
against
them
or
others
as well,
with
mostly
indifference
as
to
whether
these
beliefs
are
true.
In
Lindley
v.
Rutter,
a
policewoman
was
not
prosecuted
after
forcibly
searching
a
female
prisoner
and
removing
her brassiere,
although
there
was
no
reason
to
believe
that
the
prisoner
was
at
risk
of
committing
suicide.
1
42
The
action
appeared
to
have
been performed
mostly
out
of
routine
and
with
little
to
no
effort
taken
to
ascertain
the
truth
of
that
belief.
43
It
is
concerning
that
many
state
agents
do
in
fact
demonstrate
such
an
attitude
of
indifference
in
forming
such
beliefs,
possibly
deriving
from
the
thought
that
they
are
effectively
immune
from
investigation
as
long
as
they
can
say
that
their
beliefs
are
honest.1
44
The
artificial
cognitive
separation
of
"belief'
and
"force,"
with
English
law
ascribing
a reasonableness
element
only
to
the
latter
and
not
the
former,
is
also
undesirable.
First,
it
is
unclear
why
a
person
who
acts
on
an
unreasonably
mistaken
belief
with
reasonable
force
would
be
allowed
a full
defense
while
a
person
who
acts
on
a
correct
factual
belief
with
excessive
force
would
be
granted
no
defense
whatsoever.
Second,
the
human
cognitive
thought
process
simply
cannot
be
categorized
in
such
a
manner,
and
the existing
legislation
has
caused
much
confusion
and
uncertainty.
A
person,
when
acting
in
self-defense,
can
have
a
range
of
beliefs
that
he
is
considering
before
acting-for
example,
the
woman
who
suspects
she
is
being
followed
in
the
example
above
may
have
a
variety
of
likely
threats
she
is
considering
in
her
head
before
she
chooses
to
make
a
pre-emptive
strike
to
guarantee
her
own
safety.
It
is hence
unclear
which
"belief'
the
courts
will
find
to
be
genuine
and
use
as
the
basis
for
assessing
reasonable
force,
and
has
led
to
much
judicial
uncertainty.
This
problem
subtly
arose
in
the
Oye
case
mentioned
above,
in
which
it
was
so
difficult
to
specifically
pinpoint
what
the
exact
"threat"
the
defendant
perceived
himself
to
be
facing
was,
that
the
141.
SEEKING
SECURITY,
supra
note
6,
at
273.
142.
Lindley
v.
Rutter
[1981]
QB
128
(Eng.);
SEEKING
SECURITY,
supra
note
6,
at
290.
143.
SEEKING
SECURITY,
supra
note
6,
at
290.
144.
Id.
at
289.
2018]
397
COLUMBIA
HUMAN
RIGHTS
LAW
REVIEW
court
simply
held
that
the
standards
of
reasonableness
could
not
be
set
and
disallowed
the
defense.
While
the
ruling
was
understandable,
it
generates
much
legal
uncertainty,
as
the
way
the
judges
made
the
ruling
in
Oye
was
through
a
convoluted
reinterpretation
of
legislation
that
was
clearly
contrary
to
its
wording.
145
A
similar
problem
arose in
R
v.
Martin,
in
which
a
man,
suffering
from
paranoid
personality
disorder
and
believing
two
burglars
were
going
to
attack
him,
shot
one
of
the
burglars
and
was
found
to
have used
unreasonable
force.
The
court
failed
to
take
into
account
his
increased
perception
of
risk
as
a
result
of
his
disorder,
likely due
to
the
vague
nature
of
"risk"
in
ascertaining
a
particular
belief.146
Hence,
if
the
purpose
of
the
current
law
is
to
increase
legal
certainty,
it
has
clearly failed
to
do
so
as
the
cognitive
compartmentalization
of
"belief'
and
"force"
into
separate
categories
has
contributed
unnecessary
complexity
which seldom
mirrors
actual
circumstances.
The
2008
legislation
included
additional
clarification
as
to
what
constitutes
"reasonable
force,"
possibly
to
counter
the
undesirable
cognitive
separation
in
the
common
law.
14 7
It states
that
where
a
person
acts
in
a
way
that
he
"honestly
and
instinctively
thought
was
necessary,"
this
fact
serves
as
"strong
evidence"
that
the
force
used
was
reasonable.
14 8
This
is,
once
again,
problematic
for
similar
reasons
as
those
mentioned
previously.
A
person
who
is
"honestly
and
instinctively"
violent
will
be
held
to
have
reasonable
force,
even
though
one
would
not consider
an
inherent
predisposition
towards
violence
to
be
a
mitigating
factor
in
any
way.
The
excessively
inclusive
nature
of
self-defense
as
a
complete
defense
to
any
form
of
homicide
is
particularly
noticeable
when
held
in
comparison
with
other
common
defenses
that
are
similar.
Unlike
self-defense,
which
appears
unjustly
broad,
the
defense
of
duress
is
unjustly
narrow
and
oddly
so-it
does
not
extend
to
charges
of
murder,
requires
the
defendant
to
be
held
to
a
strictly
reasonable
standard,
and
also
the
defendant
will
not
be
able
to
plead
duress
where
there
are
alternatives
to
the
criminal
act,
even
if
the
defendant
145.
See
R
v.
Oye
[2013]
EWCA
Crim
1725,
[2014]
1
W.L.R.
3354,
[2]
(Eng.);
Andrew
Turnbull,
Delusions
and
Self-Defence:
Implications
of
the
Decision
in
R
v
Oye
[2013]
EWCA
Crim
1725,
CHARTER
CHAMBERS
(Oct.
25,
2013),
http://www.charterchambers.com/news/2013/10/25/delusions-and-self-defence-
implications-of-the-decision-in-r-v-oye-2013-ewca-crim-1725-by-andrew-turnbull/
[https://perma.cc/2UJW-UBFT].
146.
See
R
v.
Martin
[2001]
EWCA
Crim
2245
(Eng.).
147.
Criminal
Justice
and
Immigration
Act
2008,
c.4,
§76(7)(b)
(Eng.).
148.
Id.
398
[
49.3:1
As
Long
as
They
Honestly
Believe
is
for
any
reason
incapable
of
identifying
or
using
such
alternatives.
14 9
This
is
likely
a
result
of
the
preconceived
idea
that
duress
is
naturally
an
excusatory
defense,
whereas
self-defense
is
a
justification.
However,
self-defense
based
on
a
mistaken
belief
is
also
an
excuse.
It
is
thus
important
to
note
that
self-defense
does
not
simply
act
as
a
justification
and
allow
it
a
broad spectrum
of
effect
as
a
result,
and
recognize
that
the
excusatory
nature
of
mistaken
self-defense
warrants
that
it
should
be
an
area
that
is
relatively
restricted
like
the
defense
of
duress
is.
D.
An
Obsolete
Basis
Finally,
the
United
Kingdom's
unwillingness
to
budge
from
this
position
is
particularly
odd
given
the
fact
that
its
basis
was
in a
case
that
had
already
been
overruled
in
2003.
As
stated
in
Part
I.B,
the
honest
belief
doctrine
of
English
self-defense
law
can
be
attributed
to
Gladstone
Williams.
5
o
In
Williams,
a
man
(known
only
as
M
in
the
judgment)
saw
a
youth
robbing
a
woman in
a
street.
M
tried
to
catch
the
youth,
who
broke
free
from
his
grasp,
so
M
knocked
him
to
the
ground.
The
defendant
then
arrived
at
the
scene
and
only
witnessed
the
later
stages
of
the
accident."'
M
told
the
defendant,
untruthfully,
that
he
was
a police
officer
who
was
arresting
the
youth
for
robbing
the
woman.
The
defendant
asked
M
to
show
him
a
warrant
card,
which
he
could
not
produce.1
5 2
They
got
into
a
struggle,
during
which
the
defendant
punched
M
in
the
face.1'
The
defendant
was charged
with
assault
occasioning
actual
bodily
harm
under
the
Offences
Against
the
Person
Act
§
47."'
At
trial,
the
judge
directed
the
jury
that
the
availability
of
the
defense
should
be
determined
by
whether
the
defendant
had
an honest
belief,
based
on
reasonable
grounds,
that
M
was
acting
unlawfully."'
As
the
jury
found
the
defendant's
belief
unreasonable,
the
defendant
was
convicted.
He
appealed
on
the
basis
that
the
judge
had
misdirected
the
jury.
156
The
Court
of
Appeal
subsequently
held
that
the
trial
judge
should
have
directed
the
jury
to
find
the
defendant's
state
of
mind
149.
See
R
v.
Hudson and
Taylor
[19711
2 QB
202
(Eng.).
150.
R
v.
Williams
(Gladstone)
1987]
3
All
ER
411
(Eng.).
151.
Id.
152.
Id.
153.
Id.
154.
Offences
Against
the
Person
Act
1861,
24
&
25
Vict.
c.
100,
§
47
(UK).
155.
R
v.
Williams
(Gladstone)
[1987]
3
All
ER
411
(Eng.).
156.
Id.
2018]
399
COLUMBIA
HUMAN
RIGHTS
LAW
REVIEW
with
regards
to
his
honest
belief,
and
not
consider
whether
or
not
it
is
reasonable
except
for
the
purpose
of
determining
if
he
held
that
belief
at
all.
In
determining
this standard,
Lord
Chief
Justice
Lane
mainly
applied
the
principle
in
Director
of
Public
Prosecutions
v.
Morgan,
where the
House
of
Lords
decided
that
a
man
who
engaged
in
sexual
intercourse
with
a
woman
who
did
not
consent
was
not
guilty
of
rape
as
long
as
he honestly
believed
that
she consented,
irrespective
of
whether
that
belief
was
reasonable."'
The
shocking
decision
in
Morgan
has
thankfully
been
overruled
upon
the
enactment
of
the
Sexual
Offences
Act
2003,
which
required
one
to
have
an
honest and
reasonable
belief
in
consent
to
be
acquitted
of
a
sexual
crime.
5
'
The
doctrine
of
honest
belief
for
cases
of
self-defense,
however,
remained.
Hence,
the
arguable
origin
of
the
"honest
belief'
doctrine
in
self-defense
had
little
reason
behind
it apart
from
the
application
of
a
superior
court's
holding
which
has
long
been
overruled.
Therefore,
this
Note
asserts
that
the
doctrine
should
be
reconsidered,
in
light
of
its
inherent
problems,
doctrinal
uncertainty,
and
failure
to
reflect
important
social
developments.
III.
POTENTIAL
SOLUTIONS
A.
An
Honest
and
Reasonable
Belief
A
simple
solution
to
the
above
problems
would
naturally
be
to
change
the
standard
of
belief
that
a
defendant
must
have
in
cases
of
mistaken
belief
in
self-defense
to
an
honest
and
reasonable
one
similar
to
the
standard
in
English
tort
law
established
in
Ashley.
159
While
it
is
certainly
not
true
that
adding
the requirement
of
reasonable
belief
will
stop
all
cases
of
unreasonable
police
brutality
or
racist
beliefs
from
avoiding
conviction,
as
demonstrated
in
the
extremely
controversial
New
York
case
of
People
v.
Goetz,
such a
requirement
would
still
at
the
very
least
allow
for
the
defendants'
beliefs
to
be
scrutinized
on
an
objective
level
before
the
jury.
160
Naturally, requiring
a
standard
of
honest
and reasonable
belief
for
cases
of
mistaken
belief in
self-defense
could
pose
certain
157.
Director
of
Public
Prosecutions
v.
Morgan
[1975]
UKHL
3,
[1976]
AC
182
(appeal
taken
from
U.K.).
158.
Sexual
Offences
Act
2003,
c.
42,
§
1(1)
(U.K.).
159.
Ashley
v.
Chief
Constable
of
Sussex
[20081
UKHL
25,
[2008]
1
AC
962
(appeal
taken
from
Eng.).
160.
People
v.
Goetz,
68
N.Y.2d
96,
113
(N.Y.
1986).
[49.3:1
400
As
Long
as
They
Honestly
Believe
issues,
such
as
hindsight
bias.
A
twelve-member
jury
made
up
of
calm
and
composed
individuals
not
facing
a
situation
involving
potential
threat
and
looking
in
hindsight
at
the
situation
may
have
little
sympathy
for
the
defendant
in
deciding
whether
or
not
the belief
that
the
defendant
had
formed
in
a
high-tension
situation
was
in
fact
"reasonable."
In
order
to
resolve
this
potential
problem,
the
reasonableness
standard
for
finding
"honest
and
reasonable
belief'
should
focus
on
whether
or
not
the
way
in
which
the belief
was
formed was
reasonable,
rather
than
the
belief
itself.
Using
the
standard
of
an
honest
belief
with
a
"reasonable
basis"
for
establishing
said belief
is
beneficial
in
three
ways.
First,
it
allows
the
jury
flexibility
while
minimizing
the
hindsight
bias
that
would
naturally
be
pervasive
in
an
assessment
of
the
belief
itself,
by
allowing
the
jury
to
scrutinize
the
thought
process
that
went
behind
the
belief.
Such
a
method
will
also
consume
limited
resources,
as
the
jury
can
simply
make
use
of
the
defendant's
testimony
of
their
perception
at
the time
and
the
corroborating
evidence
to
come
to
a
determination
of
its
reasonableness.
Second,
this
allows
for
police
officers
to
be
held
to
a
higher
standard
of
reasonable
belief
without
creating
a
different
set
of
standards
for
police
officers
on
duty
entirely,
as
the
jury
would
take
into
account
the
police
officer's
training
and
experience
in
determining
whether
the
belief
made
had
a
reasonable
basis.
If
the
jury
finds
that
the
defendant
had
created
such
a
belief
with
reckless
indifference
as
to
whether
or
not
it
is
true,
as
is
a
problem
that
commonly
plagues
cases
of
unreasonable
brutality,
such
a
belief
shall
not
be
found
to
be
reasonable.
16
1
Finally,
it
allows
the
judges
a
certain
amount
of
discretion
and
control
in
deciding
cases
by
giving
them
the
ability
to
instruct
the
jury
as
to
what
kinds
of
bases
should
or
should
not
be
considered
"reasonable,"
which
can
influence
a
new
series
of
case
law
setting
forth
what
constitutes
a reasonable
basis
for
belief.
The
Parliament
and
English
courts
have
made
a
good
attempt
at
punishing
defendants
in
situations
where
their
beliefs
were
made
in
a
way
that
was
potentially
more culpable,
by
denying
defendants
the
defense
where
their
mistaken
beliefs
were
a
result
of
an
intoxicated
state
of
mind,
where
the
intoxication
was
voluntary.
6
However,
a
blanket
ban
of
the
defense
on
all
cases
involving
mistaken
beliefs
arising
from
voluntary
intoxication
is
premised
on
the
assumption
that
when
a
person
is
voluntarily
intoxicated,
any
161.
As
suggested
in
SEEKING
SECURITY,
supra
note
6,
at
291.
162.
See
Criminal
Justice
and
Immigration
Act
c.4,
§
76(5)
(Eng.).
2018]
401
COLUMBIA
HUMAN
RIGHTS
LAW
REVIEW
mistaken
belief
arising
from
it
is
automatically
unreasonable,
no
matter
how
sympathetic
the
situation
may
be.
Yet,
the
fact
that
the
courts
are
willing
to
deny
the
defense
on
the
basis
of
an
unreasonable
belief-even
if
they
define
unreasonableness
as
simply
any
belief
arising
from
voluntary
intoxication-shows
that
the
English
courts
are not
automatically
predisposed
against
incorporating
the
idea
of
denying
the
defense
on
the
basis
of
an
honest
but
unreasonable
belief.
Therefore,
it
may
not
be
so
unlikely
for
the
courts
to
reject
this
rigid
definition
of
unreasonableness
and
adopt
a
reasonableness
standard
that
gives
more
discretion
to
the
jury's
assessment
of
the
circumstances
of
the
case,
while
still
controlling
a
few
factors
that
the
jury must
consider.
B.
Abolishing
Affirmative
Defense
to
Manslaughter
Alternatively,
if
such
a
change
is
not
feasible
at
this
point
in
time,
it
may
still
be
possible
to
ensure
that
cases
of
self-defense
in
which
a
mistaken
belief
in
a
threat
caused
death
are
properly
scrutinized
on
the
level
of
reasonableness
by
excluding
self-defense
from
being
pled
entirely
for
manslaughter
by
gross
negligence.
When
a
person
acts
in
legitimate
or
reasonable
self-defense,
they
would
simply
not
fulfill
the
elements
of
gross
negligence
manslaughter
anyway,
as
their
actions
would
not
have
been
considered
by
a
reasonable
jury
to
have
been
in
gross
breach
of
duty.
There
is
thus
little
reason
for
an
affirmative
defense
of
self-defense
to
be
available
to
a
charge
of
gross
negligence
manslaughter,
and
the
only
purpose
it
does
serve
is
to
provide
people
who
grossly
and
unreasonably
believed
they
had
to
use
fatal
violence
against
an
innocent
person
to
be
excused
entirely
from
being
convicted
of
any
form
of
homicide.
As
of 2017,
there
has
yet
to be
direct
authority
in
which
a
defendant
who
kills
another
as
a
result
of
an
honest
but
unreasonable
belief
is
either
convicted
or
acquitted
of
a
gross
negligence
manslaughter
charge.
When
such
a
case
arises,
this
Note
implores
that
the
English
courts
set
a
precedent
to
deny
the
defense
altogether
for
charges
of
gross
negligence
manslaughter.
C.
Partial
Defense
of
Excessive
Self-Defense
We
have
discussed
in
Part
II
the
problematic
nature
of
separating
"belief'
and
"force"
into
separate
cognitive
categories
and
ascribing
the
stringent
requirement
of
reasonableness
only to
the
latter.
A
major
problem
with
English
self-defense
law
is
that
it
operates
in
an
"all-or-nothing"
manner-a
defendant
is
either
402
[49.3:1
As
Long
as
They
Honestly
Believe
absolved
of
all
liability,
or
is
convicted
with
full
culpability.
In
cases
of
self-defense,
this
means
that
where
the
defendant
acted
on
a
grossly
unreasonable
mistaken
belief
with
what
might
be
considered
"reasonable
force"
in
light
of
that
mistaken
belief,
causing
death,
he
will
be
allowed
to
plead
a
full
defense,
whereas
a
defendant
who
acted
on
a correct
belief
but
used
excessive
force
given
that
belief,
causing
death,
will
be
convicted
of
murder.
There
is,
again,
little
reason
why
this
is
the
case,
and
this
once
again
demonstrates
the
undesirably
absolute
and
formalistic
distinctions
prevalent
in
English
criminal
law.
Imperfect
self-defense
exists
as a
partial
defense
in
many
sophisticated
jurisdictions
around
the
world,
including
Commonwealth
countries
which
have
based
their
self-defense
laws
on
English
law
yet
departed
since.
Many
states
of
the
United
States,
such
as
California
and
Maryland,
recognize
the
doctrine
of
imperfect
self-defense
at
common
law.'
63
Two
European
countries
also recognize
self-defense
through
the
use
of
excessive
force
as
a
defense
in
itself.
The
German
Criminal
Code
provides
in
§
33
that
if
a
defendant
uses
more
force
than
necessary
out
of
"confusion,
fear
or
fright",
a
full
defense
of
"self-defense-excess"
is
still
available.'
64
In
the Netherlands,
the
Dutch
Criminal
Code
also
excuses
excessive
force
if
the
force
arose
as
the
result
of
a
"strong
emotion
brought
about
by
the
attack."'
Australia
recognizes,
in
statutory
form,
a
partial
defense
to
murder
that
reduces
the
offence
to
manslaughter
if
the
defendant
used
disproportionate
force
that
resulted
in
death.
6
6
It
is
potentially
arguable
that
such
a
partial
defense
has
already
been
covered
by
the
now
statutory
defense
of
"loss
of
control"
in
English criminal
legislation.1
67
The Coroners
and
Justice
Act
2009
allows
a
partial
defense
to
a
person
who
kills
another
to
have
their
conviction
reduced
to
one
of
manslaughter
provided
that
the
crime
was
committed
in
loss
of
self-control,
with
a
"qualifying
trigger,"
and
with
a
"normal
degree
of
tolerance
and
self-restraint."
6
A
"qualifying
trigger"
is
defined
as
either
a
fear
of
"serious
violence"
(which
overlaps
with
self-defense),
or
anything
done
or
said
that
constituted
circumstances
of
"an extremely
grave
character"
that
caused
the
163.
State
v.
Humphrey,
921
P.2d
1
(Cal.
1996);
State
v.
Faulkner,
483
A.2d 759,
769
(Md.
1984).
164.
COMPARATIVE
CONCEPTS,
supra
note
87,
at
147.
165.
Id.
166.
Criminal
Law
Consolidation
Act
1935
(SA) s
15
(Austl.).
167.
Coroners
and
Justice
Act
2009,
c.
25,
§
54(1)
(Eng.).
168.
Id.
2018]
403
COLUMBIA
HUMAN
RIGHTS
LAW
REVIEW
defendant
to
have
"a
justifiable
sense
of being
seriously
wronged."
69
However,
such
a defense
is
insufficient
as
it
still
subjects
the
use
of
force
by
the
defendant
to
a
reasonableness
requirement
that
is
not
explicitly
stated
to
be one.
By
holding
the
defendant
to
the
standard
of
a person
with
a
"normal
degree
of
tolerance
and
self-restraint,"
the
court
has barred
the
defense
from people
who
fail
to
reach such
a
standard.
While
it
may
be
understandable
for
courts
to
be
reluctant
to
extend
a
partial
defense
to
someone
who
knowingly
killed
another
after
being
provoked
when
no
reasonable
person
would,
it
is
less
understandable
why
a
full
defense
can
be
granted
where
the
unreasonableness
was
in
the
mistaken
belief
rather
than
the
force
used.
The
best
way
to
smooth
out
this
undesirable
cognitive
distinction
would
be
to
include
a
reasonableness
requirement
for
both
the
"belief'
and
"force"
assessments,
and
include
a
partial
defense
if
either
requirement
fails
to
reach
the
"reasonableness"
threshold.
A
concern
about
having
a
partial
defense
was
raised
in
Australia
in
Zecevic
v.
Director
of Public
Prosecutions,
a
case
that
abolished
the
defense
at
common
law,
though
it
was
subsequently
implemented
statutorily.
The concern
was
that
it
would
confuse
juries
to
be
asked
to
consider
both
questions
of
"full"
and
partial
self-defense
in a
way
that
might increase
the
risk
of
juries
agreeing
on
partial
self-defense
as
a compromise
verdict
when
in
fact
none
believed
in
it.
170
The
problem
of
compromise
verdicts
is
often
faced
in
many
criminal
charges
involving
several
crimes
of
varying
levels
of
severity-such
as
murder
and
manslaughter,
and
crimes
which
constitute
misdemeanors
and
felonies
in
the
United
States.
The
way
to
solve
this
problem, however,
is
through
better jury
instructions
rather
than
abolishing
the
principle
of
having
different
charges
and
defenses
for
different
situations.
D.
Inspiring
Reform:
The
European
Court
of
Human
Rights
Many
methods
of
reform
in
English
self-defense
law
have
been
debated
and
discussed
in
the past,
but
this
has
yet
to
lead
to
any
changes
in
English
self-defense
law
that
can
better
protect
the
rights
of
innocent
individuals
not
to
be
attacked
by
police
officers
or
other
civilians
who
have
unreasonably
or
indifferently
believed
that
they
were
threatening.
Now
that
the
doctrine
of self-defense
has
been
fully
set
out
in
Parliamentary
legislation
rather
than
just
the
common
law,
169.
Id.
§
55.
170.
Zecevic
v.
Director
of
Public
Prosecutions
[19871
HCA
26;
(1987)
162
CLR
645;
(1987)
71
ALR 641;
(1987)
61
ALJR
375
(Austl.).
404
[49.3:1
As
Long
as
They
Honestly
Believe
the
job
of
the
courts
to
amend
it
has
become
much
more
difficult.
Hence,
I
believe
that
currently
the
most
effective
way
to
stimulate
any
reform
in
self-defense
law
today
would
be
for
the
Strasbourg
Court
to
decide
that
English
law,
as
it
stands,
is
incompatible
with
the
ECHR
and
require
that
the
United
Kingdom
change
the
existing
laws
through
the
doctrine
of
positive
obligations.
Taking
into account
the
language
used
in
Article
2,
and
the
position
of
the
Strasbourg
Court in
McCann
v.
United
Kingdom
and
other
related
cases,
it
does
appear
that
English
law-which
in
its
current
state
fails
to
convict
police
officers
who
kill
innocents
with
reckless
indifference-is
a
violation
of
Article
2.
The
Article
states
that
deprivation
of
life
is
always
a
violation
unless
it
is
done
so
with
the
"use
of
force
which
is
no
more
than
absolutely
necessary."
17
1
In
McCann,
the
Strasbourg
Court
interpreted
that
provision
of
Article
2
to
mean
that
where
state
actors use
lethal
force
against
an
innocent
without
reasonable
belief
in
the
existence
of
a
threat,
such
action
constitutes
a
violation
of
the
state's
obligations
under
Article
2.
In
Angelova
and
Iliev
v.
Bulgaria,
the
Strasbourg
Court
stated
that
the
core
of
Article
2(1)
requires
states
to
put
into
place
"effective
criminal
law
provisions
to
deter the
commission
of
offences
against
the
person."
1
72
With
that
in mind,
the
fact
that
English
self-defense
law
allows
unreasonable
belief
to
justify
taking
the
life
of
another
insufficiently
protects
potential
victims-which
the
United
Kingdom
has
a
positive
obligation
to
do
under
Article
2-means
that
it
can
be
established
that
U.K.
law
does
not
sufficiently
deter
people
from
hurting
others
on
an unreasonable
belief
in
a
threat.
The
Strasbourg
Court
has
yet
to
make
such
a
judgment,
but
if
it
ever
rules
that
the
English
law
is
incompatible
with the
United
Kingdom's
positive
obligations
under
the
ECHR,
the United
Kingdom
will
be
obliged
under
international
law
to
abide
by
the
ruling
and
amend
its
laws.'
Similarly,
the
domestic
U.K.
courts
can
influence
Parliament
to
reform
existing
self-defense
laws
through
the
Human
Rights
Act
1998,
which
is
a
way
for
the
English
courts
to
enforce
human rights
law
of
the
ECHR.'
74
Given
the
specificity
of section
76
of
the
Criminal
Justice
and
Immigration
Act
and
the
principle
of
Parliamentary
sovereignty,
the
courts
do
not
have
the
power
to
interpret
a
171.
European
Convention,
supra
note
12,
art.
2.
172.
Angelova
and
Iliev
v.
Bulgaria,
App.
No.
55523/00,
1
93
(Eur.
Ct. H.R.
July
26,
2007),
available
at
http://www.echr.coe.int.
173.
European
Convention,
supra
note
12,
art.
2.
174.
Human
Rights
Act
1998,
c.
42
(UK).
405
2018]
COLUMBIA
HUMAN
RIGHTS
LAW
REVIEW
"reasonable
belief'
requirement
into
the
existing
law
of
self-defense
against
the
text
of
the
legislation,
as
this
power is
neither
inherent
in
the
courts
nor
conferred
upon
them
by
legislation."'
Nonetheless,
the
courts
can
still
issue
a
Declaration
of
Incompatibility under
section
4
of
the
Human
Rights
Act,
which
can politically
pressure
Parliament
into
amending
its
existing
legislation.
However,
this
is
more
easily
said
than
done.
The
relationship
between
the
United
Kingdom
and
the
Strasbourg
Court
has
been
noticeably
strained
in
the
past
decade,
resulting
in
a
situation
where
Strasbourg
has
refrained
from
putting
excessive
pressure
on
the
United
Kingdom.
There have been
increasing
accusations
within
the
United
Kingdom
of
the
Strasbourg
Court
acting
as
"mission
creep,"
meaning
that
Strasbourg
is
deliberately
creating
excessive
rights
that
infringe
upon
the
sovereignty
of
the
United
Kingdom
to
determine
its
own
standard
of
human rights
protection."'
As
a
result,
the
United
Kingdom
has
demonstrated
some
reluctance
in
enforcing
the
Strasbourg
Court's
judgments
that
it
deems
excessive,
such
as
in
the
case
of
Hirst
v.
United Kingdom,
where
Strasbourg
held
that
the
legislative
ban
in
the
United
Kingdom
against
allowing
convicted
prisoners
to
vote
was
a
violation
of
Article
3
of
Protocol
1
of
the
ECHR
(right
to
free
elections)."
1 7
It has
been
over
a
decade
since
that
judgment,
and
the United
Kingdom
has
still
not amended
its
laws
to
implement
the
ruling
in
Hirst.
The
Conservative
Party,
which
is
the
current
ruling
party,
has
also
threatened
(and
recently
committed)
to
replace
the
Human
Rights
Act
1998
with
a
"British
Bill
of
Rights"
of
an
undecided
character.
1 7 8
It
is
hence
likely
that
Strasbourg
is
concerned
that
further
attempts
to
pressure
the
United
Kingdom
would
result
in
the
United
Kingdom
withdrawing
from
the
ECHR
or
ignoring
Strasbourg
175.
For
more
information
on
the
doctrine
of
Parliamentary
sovereignty,
see
Parliamentary
Sovereignty,
UK
PARLIAMENT,
https://www.parliament.uk/
about/how/role/sovereignty/
[https://perma.cc/QXF4-NT3P].
176.
The
Conservative
Party,
Protecting
Human
Rights
in
the
UK:
The
Conservatives'
Proposals
for
Changing
Britain's
Human
Rights
Laws,
https://www.conservatives.com/-/media/files/downloadable%20files/human-rights.
pdf
[https://perma.ce/CZ7K-SD5W].
177.
Hirst
v.
United
Kingdom
(No.
2),
2005-IX
Eur.
Ct.
H.R.
187;
Ed
Bates,
The
Continued
Failure
to
Implement
Hirst
v
UK,
EJIL:
TALK!
(Dec.
15,
2015),
http://www.ejiltalk.org/the-continued-failure-to-implement-hirst-v-uk/
[https://perma.cc/F7KU-8JTB].
178.
Will
the
Human
Rights
Act
be
Scrapped?,
THE
WEEK
(Jan.
25,
2017),
http://www.theweek.co.uk/63635/will-the-human-rights-act-be-scrapped
[https://perma.cc/9YM8-WFPM].
406
[49.3:1
As
Long
as
They
Honestly
Believe
jurisprudence
entirely.
However,
even
if
the
United
Kingdom
does
repeal
the
Human
Rights
Act,
it
will
still
be
subject
to
Strasbourg
jurisprudence
as
long
as
it
remains
signatory
to
the
ECHR,
from
which
Prime
Minister
Theresa
May
has
pledged
that
it
will
not
withdraw."'
Additionally,
there
has
not
been
any
complaint
regarding
Strasbourg's
"mission
creep"
where
its
decisions
regarding
Article
2's
right
to life
is
concerned.
We
should
thus
proceed
on
the
basis
that
Strasbourg
still
does
and
will
continue
to
have
influence
in
enforcing
the
Articles
of
the
Convention
that
are
most
closely
related
to
English
self-defense
law-Articles
2
and
3.
1.
The
Importance
of
Positive
Obligations
in
the
ECHR
As
stated
in
Part
I,
the
"right
to
life"
under
the
ECHR
not
only
imposes
a
negative
obligation
upon
signatory
states
to
refrain
from
infringing
upon
individual
rights,
but
also
a
positive
obligation
to
enforce
laws
that
protect
the
rights
of
individuals
within
their
borders."so
This
means
that
when
police
officers,
who
are
state
agents,
act
in
their
course
of
duty
in
a
manner
that
unnecessarily
deprives
individuals
of
their
right
to
life,
there
are
two
different
ways
for
Strasbourg
to
assess
the
case
as a
violation
of
the
Convention.'
First,
the
Strasbourg
Court
can
assess
if
the
police
action
taken
was
in
breach
of
the
state's
negative
obligation
not
to
unnecessarily
deprive
a
person
of
their
right
to
life.
In
other
words,
this
would
be
an
examination
into
whether
the
state's
executive
action
was
a
violation
of
the
state's
negative
obligation.
This
was
the
assessment
made
in
McCann
and
in
most
cases
involving
actions
involving
police
brutality
that
were
brought
before
Strasbourg.
1 8
2
However,
it
is also
possible
for
Strasbourg
to
assess
the
state's
potential
violation
of
its
positive
obligations
in
terms
of
either
a
failure
to
prosecute
the
crime,
or
the
failure
to
implement
a
sufficiently
rigorous
set
of
laws
that
would
prevent
or
deter
the
unnecessary
deprivation
of
human
life.
In
Makaratzis
v.
Greece,
the
Grand
Chamber
of
Strasbourg
ruled
that
signatory
states
have
a
positive
duty
to
incorporate
an
appropriate
legal
framework
defining
179.
Adam Wagner,
BREAKING:
Theresa
May
Will
NOT
Try
to
Take
UK
Out
Of
European
Convention
on
Human
Rights,
RIGHTSINFO
(June
30,
2016),
http://rightsinfo.org/breaking-theresa-may-will-not-try-leave-european-
convention-human-rights/
[https://perma.cc/2CPF-B68D].
180.
POSITIVE
OBLIGATIONS,
supra
note
14,
at
203.
181.
European
Convention,
supra
note
12,
art.
10.
182.
See
Bubbins
v.
United
Kingdom,
2005-Il
(extracts)
Eur.
Ct.
H.R.
171.
407
2018]
As
Long
as
They
Honestly
Believe
of
self-defense
in
relation
to
positive
obligations
is
Gramadd
v.
Romania,
wherein
Romania's
failure
to
sufficiently
investigate
the
circumstances
of
an
excessive
but
non-fatal
police
shooting
and
the
domestic
courts'
subsequent
acquittal
of
the
police
officer
on
the
basis
of
self-defense
was
a
violation
of
Article
3
of
the
ECHR
(prohibition
of
inhuman
or
degrading
treatment)."'
However,
it
was
unclear
in
the
judgment
whether,
had
there
been
an
adequate
investigation
and the
defendant
still
acquitted,
Strasbourg
would
still
find
a
violation
of
Article
3.
It
is
also
unclear
whether
the
violation
of
the
positive
obligations
in
Article
3
was
a
result
of
a
failure
to
investigate,
or
the
potentially
excessive
nature
of
Romanian
law's
definition
of
self-
defense
that
may
fail
to
adequately
protect
the
rights
of
victims.
Hence,
Strasbourg's
decision
in
Grdmadd
once
again
skirted
a full
assessment
of
the
adequacy
of
domestic
self-defense
law
itself.
In
R
(Collins)
v.
Secretary
of State
for
Justice,
the
domestic
High
Court
of
the
United
Kingdom
was
tasked
to
consider
whether
U.K.
self-defense
law,
which
allowed
householders
to
employ
excessive
force
against
an
intruder,
was
a
violation
of
Article
2
of
the
ECHR.'as
While
this
was
not
a
Strasbourg
case,
the
domestic
courts
of
the
United
Kingdom
had
the
power,
through
the
Human
Rights
Act
1998,
to
issue
a
declaration
of
incompatibility
if
it
found
that
the
current
law
as
it
stood
constituted
a violation.
The
High
Court
held
that
section
43
of
the
Crime
and
Courts
Act
of
2013,
which
inserted
a
provision
within
section
76
of
the
Criminal
Justice
and
Immigration
Act
that
householders
are
allowed
to
use
excessive
force
provided
that
it
is
not
"grossly
disproportionate,"
is
not
incompatible
with
Article
2.
Section
2
of
the
Human
Rights
Act
provides
that
where
domestic
courts
are
determining
a
question
related
to
the
ECHR,
they
must
"take
into
account"
any
relevant Strasbourg
jurisprudence
and
case
law.
8 9
The
High
Court
thus
took
into account
Strasbourg
jurisprudence,
such
as
Angelova
and
Iliev
v.
Bulgaria
(where
Strasbourg
stated
that
states
must
comply
with
Article
2
by
putting
in
place
measures
that
"effectively
deter"
the
commission
of
offences
against
the
person),
and
concluded
that
domestic
criminal
law
does
187.
GrAmada
v.
Romania,
App.
No.
14974/09,
¶¶
73-75
(Eur.
Ct.
H.R.
May
11,
2014),
available
at
http://www.echr.coe.int.
188.
R
(on
the
application
of
Collins)
v.
Secretary
of
State
for
Justice
[2016]
EWHC
(Admin)
33
(Eng.).
189.
Human
Rights
Act
1998,
c.
42,
§2
(UK);
Helen
Fenwick,
What's
Wrong
with
S.2
of
the
Human
Rights
Act?,
UK
CONST.
L.
BLOG
(Oct.
9,
2012),
https://ukconstitutionallaw.org/2012/10/09/helen-fenwick-whats-wrong-with-s-2-
of-the-human-rights-act/
https://perma.cc/6EYF-Q5EL].
20181
409
As
Long
as
They
Honestly
Believe
police
officers
stationed
around
the
road
identified
de
Menezes
as a
person
who
had
a
"good
possible
likeness"
to
Osman.
Several
police
officers
followed
him
to
Stockwell
London
Underground
station.
At
this
point,
there
were
conflicting
accounts
on
whether
they
had
made
a
positive
identification,
with
some officers
stating
that
he
was
not
identical
to
Osman,
while
on
the
other
hand
another
officer
said
that
"it
was
definitely
our
man,
and
that
he
was nervous
and
twitchy."1
92
At
this
point, eyewitness
accounts
of
what
happened
exactly
were
unclear,
but
the
IPCC Stockwell
One
Report
stated
that
de
Menezes
sat
down
in
one
of
the
coaches
of a
stationary
train.
One
of
the
surveillance
officers
then
shouted
to
the
other
police
officers
that
de
Menezes
was
there.
de
Menezes
then
stood
up,
arms
down,
and
was
pinned
down
by
two
officers.
According
to
one
witness,
de
Menezes
might
have
moved
his
hand
towards
the
left-hand
side
of
his
trouser
waistband,
and
two
police
officers
(known
for
the
purposes
of
the
operation
as
Charlie
2
and
Charlie
12)
immediately
shot
him in
the
head,
killing
him.'
93
After
this
tragic
incident,
the
Independent
Police
Complaints
Commission
(IPCC)
stated
in
its
"Stockwell
Two"
report
that
Mr.
de
Menezes
"did
not refuse
to
obey
a
challenge
and
was
not
wearing
any
clothing
that
could
be
classed
as
suspicious."
19 4
The
IPCC
Stockwell
One
report
also
admitted
that
the
briefings
made
to
the
officers
were
faulty,
as
they
did
not
state
that
they
must
not
confront
the
suspect
until
they
were
sure
the
suspect's
identity
was
Osman.
After
this
unfortunate
shooting
occurred
in
2005,
the
IPCC
concluded
that
the
unfortunate
killing
was
a
result
of
mistakes
that
could
and
should
have
been
avoided."'
The
report
also
identified
a
number
of
potential
offences
that
Charlie
2
and Charlie
12,
as
well
as
the
other
officers
involved,
might
have
committed,
including
murder
and
gross
negligence
manslaughter.'
9 6
However,
the
Crown
Prosecution
Service
did
not
prosecute,
on
the
basis
that
there
was
no
realistic
prospect
of
a
conviction,
as
it
would
be
difficult
to
prove
beyond
reasonable
doubt
that
the
police officers
did
not
genuinely
believe
they
were
facing
a
192.
Richard
Edwards,
Jean
Charles
De
Menezes
Inquest:
Timeline,
TELEGRAPH
(Sept.
22,
2008),
http://www.telegraph.co.uk/news/3046015/Jean-
Charles-De-Menezes-inquest-Timeline.html
(on
file
with
the
Columbia
Human
Rights
Law
Review).
193.
Armani
Da
Silva
v.
United
Kingdom,
App.
No.
5878/08,
1$
12-19,
35-36
(Eur.
Ct.
H.R.
Mar.
30, 2016),
available
at
https://www.echr.coe.int.
194.
Id.
1
18.
195.
Id.
30.
196.
Id.
30.
411
2018]1
COLUMBIA
HUMAN
RIGHTS
LAW
REVIEW
lethal
threat.
97
Subsequently,
the
victim's
cousin,
Armani
Da
Silva
submitted
a
complaint
to
Strasbourg
alleging
that
the
United
Kingdom
had
violated
Article
2
by
failing
in
its
state
duty
to
prosecute
the
police
officers,
and
also
submitted
that
the
definition
of
self-defense
in
the
United
Kingdom
was
inadequate
as
it
does
not
require
an
honest
and
reasonable
belief."1s
The
Grand
Chamber
in
Armani
Da Silva
held
that
there
was
no
duty
for
the
Crown
Prosecution
Service
to
prosecute
the
case,
as
the
current
state
of
English
self-defense
law
was
that
an honest
and
genuine
belief
and
there
was
insufficient
evidence to
persuade
a
jury
that
there
was
no
such
honest
belief.'
9 9
It
also
ruled,
as
mentioned
in
Part
I,
that
U.K.
self-defense
law
is
similar
to
the
standard
used
by
Strasbourg
in
McCann.2
0
This
is
a
very
problematic
decision.
Strasbourg
was
requested
to
consider
whether
self-defense
law
in
the
United
Kingdom
was
inadequate,
and
it
failed
to
do
just
that.
In making
this
ruling
and
dismissing the
case
on
the
basis
that
the
Crown
Prosecution
Service
had
no
duty
to
prosecute,
Strasbourg
took
domestic
English
law
as
it
stands,
with
little
analysis
into
whether
the
law
itself
was
effective
enough
to
satisfy
the
positive
obligations
in
Article
2
of
the
ECHR.2
1
While
there
was
a
brief
discussion
on
the
law
itself,
it
was
done
through
an
incorrect
interpretation
of
the
previous
ruling
in
McCann,
without assessment
into
whether
English
law
served as
an
effective
deterrence and
was
consistent
with
Article
2.202
As
mentioned
previously,
in
McCann,
Strasbourg
indicated
that
lethal
force
used
by
state
agents
must
be
based
on
an
"honest
belief
which
is
perceived,
for
197.
Id.
1
35.
198.
Armani
Da
Silva
v.
U.K.,
App.
No.
5878/08,
(Eur.
Ct.
H.R.
Mar.
30,
2016),
available
at
https://www.echr.coe.int.
199.
Human
Rights
Europe,
United
Kingdom:
Court
Ruling
on
Jean
Charles
de
Menezes
Fatal
Police-Shooting
Complaint,
COUNCIL
OF
EUROPE
(Mar.
30,
2016),
http://www.humanrightseurope.org/2016/03/united-kingdom-
court-ruling-on-jean-charles-de-menezes-fatal-police-shooting-complaint/
[https://perma.cc/LKV9-HL6J].
200.
See
generally
McCann
v.
United
Kingdom,
21
Eur.
Ct.
H.R.
97
(1995)
(finding
that
the
principal
question
to
be
addressed
is
whether
the
person
had
an
honest
and genuine
belief
that
the
use
of
force
was
necessary);
see
also
supra
Part
I.
201.
See
generally
Armani
Da Silva
v.
U.K.,
App.
No.
5878/08,
(Eur.
Ct.
H.R.
Mar.
30,
2016),
available
at
https://www.echr.coe.int
(finding
that
the
UK
authorities
had
not
failed
in
their
procedural
obligations
under
Article
2
of
the
Convention
to
conduct
an
effective
investigation
into
the
shooting).
202.
Id.
412
[49.3:1
As
Long
as
They
Honestly
Believe
good
reasons,
to
be
valid
at
the
time"-which
clearly
means
that
the
Court
is
employing
a
"honest
and
reasonable"
test.
The
Court
in
Armani
Da
Silva
applied
the
test
in
McCann,
but
interpreted
it
as
a
"honest
and
genuine"
belief
that
was
completely
contradictory
with
its
original
textual
conception-stating
that
the
"existence
of
'good
reasons'
should
be
determined
subjectively"-and
subsequently
concluded
that
the
"honest
belief'
doctrine
in
English
law
was
not
significantly
different
from
the
test
applied
by
Strasbourg
in
McCann.
At
no
point
was
the
Angelova
and
Iliev
v.
Bulgaria
assessment-the
test
of
whether
existing
law
would
be
an
effective
deterrence-employed,
and
Strasbourg
failed
to
make
a
proper
assessment
as
to
whether
the
United
Kingdom
has
met its
positive
obligations
under
Article
2
to
implement
laws
sufficient
to
protect
the
right
to life
of
individuals
within
its
jurisdiction
even
when
expressly
asked
to
make
this
assessment.
20 3
As
seen
from
the
facts,
Armani
Da
Silva
was
an
opportunity
for
Strasbourg
to
finally
analyze
the
sufficiency
of
the
"honest
belief'
doctrine
in
U.K.
self-defense
law
and
whether
it
effectively
deters
unnecessary
deprivations
of
life
that
would
be
in
violation
of
Article
2.
The
fact
that
it
did
not
is
very
regrettable.
CONCLUSION
In
conclusion,
there
are
many
ways
in
which
English
self-
defense
law
is
problematic
and
in
clear
need
of
reform.
Its
"honest
belief'
doctrine
creates
serious
unfairness
that
cannot
be
justified,
authorizes
and
encourages
instinctive
violence
based
on
racist
beliefs,
and
is
also
doctrinally
inconsistent
with
the
existing
laws
of
homicide.
Despite
this,
the
United
Kingdom
has
yet
to
make
any
changes
and
even
legislative
codification
in
2008
simply
upheld
the
existing
common
law
on
a
document
that
had
supremacy
over
subsequent
common
law
developments.
2 04
However,
the
United
Kingdom
cannot
ignore
the
ECHR
forever,
as
a
state
that
tries
to
keep
up
its
reputation
as
an "upholder
and
promoter
of
fundamental
rights.""'
A
203.
Angelova
and
Iliev
v.
Bulgaria,
App.
No.
55523/00,
93
(Eur.
Ct.
H.R.
July
26,
2007),
available
at
http://www.echr.coe.int..
204.
Criminal
Justice
and
Immigration
Act
2008,
c.4,
§
76
(Eng.)
("The
question
whether
the
degree
of
force
used
by
D
was
reasonable
in
the
circumstances
is
to
be decided
by
reference
to
the
circumstances
as
D
believed
them
to
be
....
).
205.
London
School
of
Economics
European
Institute,
The
Implications
of
Brexit
for
Fundamental
Rights
Protection
in
the
UK
1,
5
(Feb.
25,
2016),
413
2018]
COLUMBIA
HUMAN
RIGHTS
LAW
REVIEW
Strasbourg judgment
that
finally
answers
the
question
of
whether
U.K.
law
is
a violation
of
the
ECHR can
be
the
trigger
for
Parliament
to
make
the
legislative
changes
that
the
United
Kingdom
needs.
It
seems
very
likely
that
English
law
as
it
stands
is
in
fact
inconsistent
with
the
United
Kingdom's
positive
obligations
under
Article
2,
as
it
does
not
serve as
an
effective
deterrent
for
police
officers
to
act
on
grossly
unreasonable
beliefs
or
reckless
indifference.
Ultimately,
whether
or
not
U.K.
self-defense
law
is
incompatible
with
the
positive
obligations
within
the
ECHR
should
be
a
decision
made
by
Strasbourg, not
this
Note.
However,
the
fact
remains
that
Strasbourg
should
make
that
decision,
especially
given
that
it has
been
prompted
to
do
so,
instead
of
deliberately
avoiding
the
question
as
it
did
in
Armani
Da
Silva.
We
do
not
know
when
the
next
case
will
occur
that
will
bring
the
same
question
on
the
adequacy
of
English
self-defense
law
before
Strasbourg
once
again,
but
when
it
does,
this
Note
finds
it
crucially
important
that
the
question
be
addressed.
206
http://www.1se.ac.uk/europeanInstitute/LSE-Commission/Hearing-6---The-
implications-of-Brexit-for-fundamental-rights-protection-in-the-UK.pdf
[https://perma.cc/A62B-LFLA].
206.
Id.
414
[49.3:1